Free markets

A free market is a market economy in which the forces of supply and demand are free of intervention by a government, price-setting monopolies, or other authority. A free market contrasts with a controlled market or regulated market, in which government intervenes in supply and demand through non-market methods … Continue reading

free market is a market economy in which the forces of supply and demand are free of intervention by a government, price-setting monopolies, or other authority. A free market contrasts with a controlled market or regulated market, in which government intervenes in supply and demand through non-market methods such as laws creating barriers to market entry or directly setting prices. Although free markets are commonly associated with capitalism in contemporary usage and popular culture, free markets have been advocated by market anarchistsmarket socialists, proponents of cooperatives, and advocates of profit sharing.

The definition of free market has been disputed and made complex by collectivist political philosophers and socialist economic ideas. Adam Smith discarded subjective value theory and contended that an unregulated market was prone to the rise of monopolies and was therefore not “free.”

Various forms of socialism based on, or which advocate, free markets have existed since the 19th century. Early notable socialist proponents of free-markets include Pierre-Joseph ProudhonBenjamin Tucker and the Ricardian socialists, who believed that genuinely free markets andvoluntary exchange cannot exist within the exploitative conditions of capitalism.

Léon Walras, one of the founders of the neoclassical school of economics who helped formulate the general equilibrium theory, argued that free competition could only be realized under conditions of state ownership of natural resources and land. Additionally, income taxes could be eliminated because the state would receive income to finance public services through owning such resources and enterprises.[5]

Advocates of free-market socialism, such as Jaroslav Vanek, argue that genuine free markets are not possible under conditions of private ownership over productive property because the class differences and inequalities in income and power that ensue from this arrangement enable interests of the dominant class to skew the market to their favor, either in the form of monopoly and market power, or by utilizing their wealth and resources to pass government regulations and policies that benefit their specific business interests.

Excessive disparities in income distribution emerging from private ownership are alleged by proponents of this system to lead to social instability. This requires costly corrective measures in the form of social welfare and redistributive taxation and heavy administrative costs to administer them, which weakens the incentive to work, invites dishonesty and increases the likelihood of tax evasion, thus necessitating government regulation over markets and reducing the overall efficiency of the market economy.

Friedrich Hayek popularized the classical liberal view that market economies promote spontaneous order which results in a better “allocation of societal resources than any design could achieve.”[9] According to this view, in market economies are characterized by the formation of complex transactional networks which produce and distribute goods and services throughout the economy. These networks are not designed, but nevertheless emerge as a result of decentralized individual economic decisions. The idea of spontaneous order is an elaboration on the invisible hand proposed by Adam Smith in The Wealth of Nations. Smith wrote that the individual who:

By preferring the support of domestic to that of foreign industry, he intends only his own security; and by directing that industry in such a manner as its produce may be of the greatest value, he intends only his own gain, and he is in this, as in many other cases, led by an invisible hand to promote an end which was no part of his intention. Nor is it always the worse for society that it was no part of it. By pursuing his own interest [an individual] frequently promotes that of the society more effectually than when he really intends to promote it. I have never known much good done by those who affected to trade for the [common] good.

—Adam Smith, Wealth of Nations

Smith pointed out that one does not get one’s dinner by appealing to the brother-love of the butcher, the farmer or the baker. Rather one appeals to their self-interest, and pays them for their labor.

It is not from the benevolence of the butcher, the brewer or the baker, that we expect our dinner, but from their regard to their own self-interest. We address ourselves, not to their humanity but to their self-love, and never talk to them of our own necessities but of their advantages.

—Adam Smith[10]

Supporters of this view claim that spontaneous order is superior to any order that does not allow individuals to make their own choices of what to produce, what to buy, what to sell, and at what prices, due to the number and complexity of the factors involved. They further believe that any attempt to implement central planning will result in more disorder, or a less efficient production and distribution of goods and services.

A free market is a mathematical abstraction. The concept of free market is the idea that offer and demand sets the prices of things, nothing more, and nothing less. There are no free markets anywhere in the world. Markets  in the US are far from free in the Adam Smith’s sense. The US market is heavily distorted by cartels, monopolies, subsidies, tariff and non-tariff barriers to trade, and regulations. These distortions are always in favor of the short-term interests of large corporations because they control the government trough lobbying and revolving-door politicking. A notorious and archetypal example is the GMO soybean crop which is heavily subsidized in many ways and under monopolist control of Monsanto. This situation distorts the prices of food and energy and eventually, but not very far on the future, it would be catastrophic not only for the US but for the whole human race. It might be counter intuitive but to give ever more prerogatives and power to big corporations is actually perilous to democracy and free market values, let alone the very existence of humans.

The US as a country is rich not because of free markets but because is big, it has a lot of resources, grew on the back of slave labor, and it is at the apex of an empire.

A lot of poor and destitute except a few elites is not where we might be, but where we are.

A study by the World Institute for Development Economics Research at United Nations University reports that the richest 1% of adults alone owned 40% of global assets in the year 2000, and that the richest 10% of adults accounted for 85% of the world total. The bottom half of the world adult population owned barely 1% of global wealth.
You might think that the US is rich and other countries poor because of sin against free markets and manifest destiny but actually the gap between countries is narrowing. According to current research, global income inequality peaked approximately in 1970s when world income was distributed bimodally into “rich” and “poor” countries with little overlap. Since then inequality have been rapidly decreasing, and this trend seems to be accelerating. Income distribution is now unimodal, with most people living in middle-income countries. World inequality is however increasing, possibly because of increase of within-countries inequalities

Democracy, Equality, and Redistribution

Democracy, Equality, and Redistribution

Adam Przeworski
Department of Politics
New York University
October 31, 2007

1 Introduction

Democratic citizens are not equal but only anonymous, indistinguishable by any traits they may possess. Democracy only places a veil over distinctions that exist in society. Even the one sense in which equality that can be said to characterize democracy equality before the law is derivative from anonymity: the law has to treat all citizens equally because they are
indistinguishable.

This norm of anonymity was circumvented in most early representative systems by an elaborate intellectual construction that justified… restrictions of suffrage. The argument held that the role of representatives is to promote the good of all, yet the intellectual capacity to recognize the common good and the moral qualities necessary to pursue it are not universal. These traits can be recognized by using some indicators, such as wealth, age, and gender.

Hence, relying on such indicators to restrict suffrage does not violate democratic norms. The logic of the argument is unimpeachable, but it is easy to suspect that it rationalized interests. This is the way it was perceived by those excluded, poor males and women, as they fought for political rights.

Yet even if political rights are universal, to ignore distinctions is to not to obliterate them. Democracy was a political revolution, but not an economic one. Should we be surprised that democracy turned out to be compatible with economic inequality? From its inception, representative institutions were haunted by the specter of the poor using their political rights to redistribute property. Should we be surprised that democracy did not undermine property, that the democratic revolution was never completed by being extended to the economic realm?

These three themes are developed below.

2 Aristocracy and Democracy

How did democracy reappear on the historical horizon and what did it mean to its proponents and opponents?

Since the emergence of modern democracy is the topic of Palmer’s (1959, 1964) monumental treatise, no more than a brief summary is necessary.

Palmer’s main point is that democracy was not a revolution against an existing system but a reaction against the increasing power of aristocracy. It was aristocracy that undermined monarchy; democracy outflanked it following in its footsteps. Palmer argues that (1) By the early eighteenth century, the aristocratic system of government was institutionalized in assemblies of
various forms, the participation in which was reserved to legally qualified… groups (constituted bodies) that always included hereditary nobility but in different places (countries, regions, principalities, cantons, city republics) also clergy, selected categories of burgers, and in Sweden even peasants. In all cases these bodies were politically dominated by hereditary nobility. (2) In the course of the century, these estate-based bodies increased their political influence. (3) At the same time, access to nobility, however it was de…nied in different places, became increasingly closed: nobility turned into
aristocracy. (4) The resulting aristocratic system suffered from several tensions, of which one was between birth and competence. (5) Politically crucial conflict was due to the exclusion from privilege of those who possessed all the qualifi…cations to participate wealth, talent, bearing except for birth. (6) Democracy emerged as a demand for access to these bodies, not as a movement against monarchy.

Hence, by the end of the eighteenth century, democracy was a slogan directed against legal recognition of inherited distinctions of social status.

Democrats were those who agitated against aristocrats or aristocracy.. As Dunn (2003: 10) observes, democracy was a reaction, above all, not to monarchy, let alone tyranny, but to another relatively concrete social category, initially all too well entrenched, but no longer plausibly aligned with social, economic, or even political or military, functions the nobility or aristocracy…. Democrat was a label in and for political combat; and what that combat was directed against was aristocrats, or at the very least aristocracy.”2 Thus, in 1794 a young Englishman described himself as being of that odious class of men called democrats because he disapproved of hereditary distinctions and privileged orders of every species (Palmer 1964: 22).

Could any further proof be required of the republican complexion of this system, wrote Madison in The Federalist # 39, the most decisive might be found in its absolute prohibition of titles of nobility. In France, the Constituent Assembly decided that aristocratic privilege was in conflict with the very principle of popular sovereignty (Fontana 1993: 119). The Batavian (Dutch) Republic established in 1796 required voters to swear an oath to the belief that all hereditary offices and dignities were illegal (Palmer 1964: 195). In Chile, General O’Higgins, the …first Director of the State, abolished
in 1818 all outward and visible signs of aristocracy (Collier and Sater 1006: 42).

Here is a puzzle. While democrats fought against aristocracy, either as a system of government (the original meaning of the word) or as a legal status (nobility), this struggle did not have to result in abolishing other distinctions. One distinction could have been replaced by another. The flagrant case is the Polish Constitution of 3 May 1791, which was directed against
aristocrats de…fined as large landowners, magnates, under the slogan of equality for the gentry at large (szlachta, which constituted about 10 percent of the population), while preserving a legal distinction of the latter. More generally, social traits that could serve as basis for legal distinctions were many: property owners and laborers, burgers and peasants, inhabitants of different localities, clergy and army, whites and blacks. Yet democrats turned against other distinctions. All the privileges, Sieyes (1979 [1788]: 3) declared, are thus by the nature of things unjust, despicable and contradictory to the supreme goal of all political society. From aristocracy, the enemy became any kind of particularity (Rosanvallon 2004: 37 and throughout). Thus, in far away Brazil, the four mulattoes who were hanged and quartered after the failure of the Citade da Bahia Republicana in 1798 were accused of desiring the imaginary advantages of a Democratic Republic in which all should be equal … without difference of color or condition(Palmer 1964: 513). The French Revolution emancipated Protestants and Jews and freed slaves, not only Catholic peasants.

Rosanvallon (2004: 121) claims that The imperative of equality, required to make everyone a subject of law and a full citizen, implies in effect considering men stripped of their particularistic determinants. All their differences and all their distinctions should be placed at a distance…. Yet where did the imperative of equality come from? Thinking in the rational choice terms of modern political science, one would suspect that democrats instrumentally turned against other social distinctions just to mobilize the masses against aristocracy: to gain support against aristocracy. Finer (1934: 85), for example, accuses Montesquieu of deliberately juxtaposing the Citizen to all the powers that be, either the King or the aristocracy: it was a convenient, a striking and useful antithesis; nothing could be better calculated to win the support of every man. There are facts that support this hypothesis: Tadeusz Kosciuszko in Poland made vague promises to peasants to induce them join the anti-Russian insurrection in 1794; the members of the French Convention flagrantly played up to the gallery …filled by the ordinary people of Paris; Simon Bolivar made interracial appeals to recruit for the war against Spain.

Yet it is also easy to believe that democrats truly believed that all men are equal, as the Declaration of Independence declared or that men are born equal, as the Declaration of the Rights of Man would have it. The idea of innate equality certainly preceded the actual political conflicts. It could be found already in Locke’s Second Treatise (1690) as the principle that equal Right that every Man hath, to his Natural Freedom, without being subjected to the Will or Authority of any other Man. We do not have a theory of action in which people are moved by logic, in which they do things because they cannot tolerate logical contradictions. Yet if one is willing to accept that people can be moved by ideas, democrats would have turned against other distinctions by the sheer logic of their ideology: Aristocrats are not distinct because all men are born equal; because all men are born equal, they cannot be treated differently. Abolishing other distinctions would then be a logical
outcome of the struggle against aristocracy.

The fact is that democrats turned against all distinctions. The only attribute of democratic subjects is that they have none as such. The democratic citizen is simply without qualities.6 Not equal, not homogeneous, just anonymous. Even the one sense in which equality does apply as a democratic norm, namely, before the law, is just a consequence of the principle that democratic citizens cannot be distinguished in any way. As Rousseau (1964: 129) said, the sovereign [the people united] knows only the body of the nation and does not distinguish any of those who compose it. Since citizens are indistinguishable, there is nothing by which law could possibly distinguish them. The democratic citizen is simply an individual outside society. One can say an aristocrat, a wealthy person, and male, but not an aristocratic citizen, a wealthy citizen, or a male citizen. As Sieyes (1979: 183) put it, On doit concevoir les nations sur terre comme
des individues hors de lien social.

3 Democracy and Equality

In spite of its egalitarian pedigree, I am about to argue, there is no sense in which equality could or does characterize democracy. One should not let oneself be trapped by words, Pasquino (1998: 149-150) warns, the society
without qualities
is not a society of equals; it is simply a society in which privileges do not have a juridical-institutional status or recognition.
In a scathing critique of bourgeois rights, Marx (1844: no page) characterized
this duality as follows:

The state abolishes, in its own way, distinctions of birth, social rank, education, occupation, when it declares that birth, social rank, education, occupation, are non-political distinctions, when it proclaims, without regard to these distinctions, that every member of the nation is an equal participant in national sovereignty…. Nevertheless the state allows private property, education, occupation to act in their way -i.e., as private property, as education, as occupation, and to exert the influence of their special nature.

Why then political emancipation is not a form of human emancipation, as Marx would have put it? Speci…cally, in what ways is the veil over distinctions compatible with various kinds of inequality?

Consider the different meanings in which equalityappeared in democratic ideology. Why are or would be people equal? They could be because God or nature made them so, because society makes them so, or because the law makes them so. Equality can be innate or generated by spontaneous social transformations, but it can also be instituted by law or by the use of laws.

Democratic equality may thus be a reflection of equality pre-existing elsewhere or it may be imposed by laws.

To return to the Declarations one last time, the point of departure of democrats was innate equality of human beings. Democratic equality is but a reflection of a pre-existing, natural, equality. Yet the implications of a pre-existing equality are indeterminate. As Schmitt (1993: 364) observed, From the fact that all men are men it is not possible to deduce anything specifi…c either about morality or about religion or about politics or about economics.

Even if people were born equal, they may distinguish themselves by their merits and their merits may be recognized by others. More, to maintain order, some people must at each moment exercise authority over others. As Kelsen (1988 [1929]: 17) put it, From the idea that we are all equal, ideally equal, one can deduce that no one should command another. But experience
teaches that if we want to remain equal in reality, it is necessary on the contrary that we let ourselves be commanded.

Moreover, even if all human beings are born only as such, society generates differences among them. Indeed, if their parents are unequal, they become unequal at the moment they are born. To make them equal again, a recourse to laws is necessary. Montesquieu (1995: 261) would thus observe that In the state of nature, men are born equal but they do not know how to remain so. Society makes them lose equality and they do not return to be equal other than by laws.

Yet must society make people unequal? Rosanvallon (1995: 149) documents that when the term democracy came into widespread usage in France after 1814, it connoted modern egalitarian society, not the political regimes associated with the classical Greek or Roman republics, what Tocqueville would refer to as equality of conditions. The tendency toward social equality was inevitable. Taking a theme of Marquis d’Argenson (1764), Tocqueville (1961, vol I: 41) observed that The gradual development of equality of conditions … is universal, it is durable, it escapes human intervention every day;
every event, like every man, furthers its development.
J.S. Mill noted the same in 1859: There is confessedly a strong tendency in the modern world towards a democratic constitution of society, accompanied or not by popular political institutions. Note that while Tocqueville saw political equality in the United States as a natural consequence of the equality of conditions, for Mill the fact of social equality did not have unique political consequences.

Whether modern societies must become more equal is a complex question.

What matters here is that not everyone was willing to rely on the spontaneous evolution of society to generate political equality. Robespierre thought that Equality of wealth is a chimera. (Palmer 1964: 109). Madison (Federalist #10) listed all kinds of social differences and gradations, assuming they were there to stay. Most democrats believed against Tocqueville that citizenship creates equality, rather than equals become citizens. Pasquino (1998: 109) summarizes this belief: Citizens are not simply equal before the law, in the sense in which the law does not recognize either special rights or privileges,
but they become equal by the grace of law and by law itself.

Democrats adhered to what Beitz (1989: 4) calls a simple conception of political equality, namely, the requirement that democratic institutions should provide citizens with equal procedural opportunities to influence political decisions (or, more briefly, with equal power over outcomes). Criticizing this notion, he points out that equality of the abstract leverage that procedures provide to each participant does not imply equality of the actual influence over the outcomes: the latter depends also on the distribution of the preferences and of the enabling resources. This disjunction between formal and effective political equality was a central concern in the United States and continues to be debated today. The social palliative to this divergence between formal and real influence is pluralism. The political answer, at least for Madison, was large districts.

As Mill would remark several decades later, without decent wages and universal reading, no government of public opinion is possible. Education was one instrument that would equip people to exercise their citizenship rights. Several early constitutions (of the Italian republics between 1796 and 1799, the Cádiz Constitutions of 1812) established systems of universal and free, although not compulsory, education. In the meantime, most solved the problem by restricting political rights to those who were in condition to exercise them. Yet when suffrage became universal and democracy found roots in
poorer countries, the problem reappeared with a vengeance: masses of people acquired equal procedural opportunities without enjoying the conditions necessary to exploit them. Citizenship without the conditions to exercise it is a monster that haunts contemporary democracies. The absence of the effective capacity to exercise formal political rights remains at the heart of
criticisms of the really existing democracy. To return to Marx, can people be politically equal if they are socially unequal?

But political equality is vulnerable not just to social inequality but also to speci…fically political distinctions. Democracy, according to Schmitt (1993: 372), is the identity of the dominating and the dominated, of the government and the governed, of he who commands and he who obeys. But the issue is whether the very faculty of governing does not create a distinction, a
political class. Political aristocracy was seen as much of a danger as social aristocracy. The Anti-Federalists feared that if the rulers were other than the ruled, Corruption and tyranny would be rampant as they have always been when those who exercised power felt little connection with the people.

This would be true, moreover, for elected representatives, as well as for kings and nobles and bishops… (Ketcham 1986: 18). Hence, democrats were preoccupied with duration of terms, as short as six months in New Jersey at one time, term limits, restrictions on representatives to determine their own salaries, and censuring procedures.

Yet these are palliatives. The distinction between the representatives and the represented is inherent in the representative system: parliaments seat representatives, not the people. And the very method of choosing representatives through elections, rather than by lot, is based on the belief that all people are not equally quali…fied to rule. Elections, Manin (1997) argues, are based on the assumption that the qualities necessary to govern are not universally shared and that people want to be governed by their betters. These qualities need not be associated with distinctions of birth, so that elections are not aristocratic in the eighteenth century sense. But elections are a method for selecting one’s betters and, as Manin amply documents, they are and were seen as a way of recognizing a natural aristocracy of talent, reason, or whatever else voters would see as the index of the ability to govern.

Moreover, to be represented people must be organized and organization demands a permanent apparatus, a salaried bureaucracy, a propaganda machine. Hence, Michels (1962: 270) bemoaned, some militants become parliamentarians, party bureaucrats, newspaper editors, managers of the party’s insurance companies, directors of the party’s funeral parlors, and even Parteibudiger party bar keepers. As a disillusioned French communist would write many years later, The working class is lost in administering
its imaginary bastions. Comrades disguised as notables occupy themselves with municipal garbage dumps and school cafeterias. Or are these notables disguised as comrades? I no longer know(Konopnicki 1979: 53).

To summarize, the idea that political equality reflects some pre-existing state, either of nature or society, is untenable on both logical and empirical grounds. Logically, equality pre-existing in other realms does not imply political equality.

Empirically, even if all human beings were born equal, they become unequal in society, and even if societies experienced an inevitable tendency toward equality, the existing inequalities were and are sufficient to call for political remedies. In turn, political equality instituted by law is effectively undermined by social inequality. Political equality is equality in the eyes of a third party, the state, but not in the direct relation between any two persons. In no meaning then is equality the correct way to characterize democracy. If the founders used the languages of equality, it was to justify something else, better described as anonymity, generality, or oblivion to social distinctions.

4 Do Suffrage Restrictions Violate Democratic Ideology?

Yet there is one fact that appears to undermine anonymity: restrictions of suffrage. Indeed, the French Declaration qualified… its recognition of equality in the sentence that immediately followed: Men are born equal and remain free and equal in rights. Social distinctions may be founded only upon the general good. While some early constitutions made male suffrage nearly universal, during most of the nineteenth century the right to vote and the right to be elected was con…fined to adult men who owned property, earned some amount of income, or paid some amount of taxes.

The prevalence of suffrage censitaire may appear to contradict the norm of suppressing all distinctions in society and to be incompatible with the principle of political equality. Yet, even if the arguments were convoluted, franchise restrictions were not portrayed as such by their proponents.

Consider …first the justi…cation by Montesquieu (1995: 155), who starts from the principle that All inequality under democracy should be derived from the nature of democracy and from the very principle of democracy. His example is that people who must continually work to live are not prepared for public office or would neglect their functions. As barristers of Paris put
it on the eve of the Revolution, Whatever respect one might wish to show for the rights of humanity in general, there is no denying the existence of a class of men who, by virtue of their education and the type of work to which their poverty had condemned them, is … incapable at the moment of participating fully in public affairs(cited in Crook 1996: 13). In such cases, Montesquieu goes on, equality among citizens can be lifted in a democracy for the good of democracy. But it is only apparent equality which is lifted…. The generic argument, to be found in slightly different versions, is that: (1) Representation is acting in the best interest of all. (2) To determine the best interest of all one needs reason. (3) Reason has sociological determinants: not having to work for a living (disinterest), or not being employed or otherwise dependent on others (independence). As a Chilean statesman put it in 1865, to exercise political rights it is necessary to have the intelligence to recognize the truth and the good, the will to want it, and the freedom to execute it. (A speech by Senador Abdón Cifuentes, cited in Maza Valenzuela 1995: 153). In turn, the claim that only apparent equality is being violated was built in three steps: (1) Acting in the best common interest considers everyone equally, so that everyone is equally represented. (2) The only quality that is being distinguished is the capacity to recognize the common good. (3) No one is barred from acquiring this quality, so that suffrage is potentially open to all.

The last two points are crucial. Legal distinctions of social status are valid only as indicators of the ability to govern and there are no barriers of any kind to prevent people from acquiring this ability and being relevantly indicated.

The Polish Constitution of 3 May 1791 illuminates the distinction between the democratic regime censitaire and non-democratic regime of legal distinctions. The Constitution asserts in Paragraph VI that deputies to the local parliaments … should be considered as representatives of the entire nation(italics in the original). Yet to become a deputy to the local parliaments (sejmiki, which, in turn elect deputies to the national legislature, the sejm) one had to be a member of a legally de…fined group, the gentry (szlachta). In turn, only members of the hereditary gentry could own land entitling to political rights. Hence, this was not a regime censitaire in the sense defi…ned above: (1) it barred access to politics to everyone who was not a member of a legally recognized group, the landed gentry, and (2) it barred access to the landed gentry.

In fact, the Polish justi…cation for privileging gentry was not reason but
Respect for the memory of our forefathers as founders of free government….
(Article II). Simon Bolivar used the same principle in 1819 when he offered positions of hereditary senators to the liberators of Venezuela, … to whom the Republic owns its existence(1969: 109). His celebrated speech, known
as the Discurso de Angostura, merits attention because its combination of appeals to reason with an acceptance of inequality became the hallmark of anti-democratic postures in Spanish America. Bolivar observed that most people do not know their true interests and went on to argue that Everything cannot be left to the adventure of elections: the People errs easily…. His solution was the institution of a hereditary Senate: future Senators Would learn the arts, sciences, and letters which adorn the spirit of a public man; from infancy would know to what Providence destined them…. And he had the gumption to claim that The creation of a hereditary Senate would in no way violate political equality.

Restrictions of political rights based on religion were also couched in a universalistic language, but the appeal was not to reason but to common values. From Rousseau and Kant to J.S. Mill, everyone believed that a polity can function only if it is based on common interests, norms, or values. In Latin America (indeed, also in the Spanish Constitution of 1812), the cement
holding societies together was to be Catholicism: of the 103 Latin American constitutions studied by Loveman (1993: 371), 83 proclaimed Catholicism as the official religion and 55 prohibited worship of other religions. While many arguments for restricting political rights to Catholics were openly directed against the principle of popular sovereignty it is not for people to change what God willed quite a few were pragmatic. For example, the Mexican thinker Lucas Alamán maintained in 1853 that Catholic religion deserves support by the state, even if we do not consider it as divine, because it constitutes the only common tie that connects all Mexicans, when all others are broken(cited after Gargarella 2005: 93, who provides other examples).

Restrictions on female suffrage present the most difficult issue. While early proponents of female suffrage observed that reason is not distributed along gender lines after all, some rulers had been queens (Sieyes according to Pasquino 1998: 71) the main argument against giving the right to vote to women was that, like children, they were not independent, had no will of their own. Women were already represented by the males in their households and their interests were to be represented through a tutelary, rather than an electoral, connection. Thus the justifying criterion was dependence, not sex.

Indeed, when a study in England in the 1880s discovered that almost one half of adult women lived in households in which there was no adult male, this justi…fication collapsed, and only pure prejudice retarded extending suffrage to women.

Yet why were women not independent in the same way as some men were? If women could not own property, they were legally barred from qualifying for suffrage, so this would violate the democratic ideology. But where they could and did own property in their own name, why would property ownership not be a sufficient indicator? Condorcet (1986 [1788]: 293), who defended property qualifi…cations, thought it should be: The reason for which it is believed that they [women] should be excluded from public function, reasons that albeit are easy to destroy, cannot be a motive for depriving them of a right which would be so simple to exercise [voting], and which men have not because of their sex, but because of their quality of being reasonable and sensible, which they have in common with women. And Chilean suffragettes claimed that Wives and mothers, widows and daughters, we all have time and money to devote to the happiness of Chile. (An article in El Eco, 3 August 1865, cited in Maza Valenzuela 1995: 156).

Since this is an issue about which it is easy to fall into anachronisms, let me process it through an example. Suppose that it is in the best interest of each and all people to evacuate a coastal town if a hurricane is impending and not to evacuate it if the danger is remote. A correct decision is good for everyone: all men, women, and children. The correct decision can be
reached only by people who can interpret weather forecasts. This excludes children, so that the decision should be made by parents in the best interest of children. I suspect that with some quibbles about where to draw the age line most people today would accept this reasoning: all contemporary democratic constitutions do. But why should only men participate in making
this decision? If the reason is that women are barred from taking meteorology courses in school, then we are back to the 1791 Poland. But suppose they do take such courses. Now the argument must be that even if they had the same capacity to exercise reason, women would always follow the views of their male protectors, independently of their own opinions. This is then
another sociological assumption, in addition to those that tied reason to property, income, or education.

Now, Schumpeter (1942: 244) argued that if any distinction is accepted, then the principle of making such distinctions must be as well: The salient point is that, given appropriate views on those and similar subjects, disquali…cations on ground of economic status, religion and sex will enter into the same class with disquali…cations which all of us consider compatible with
democracy.
Yet each distinction is based on a speci…c assumption for example, that 12-year olds are not prepared to vote tying it to the capacity to exercise reason. Obviously, today we would and do reject most such assumptions, although not those based on age or legally certi…fied sanity. Moreover, as we will see below, some such assumptions were driven by
only thinly veiled self-interest. But if these assumptions are accepted, then restrictions of suffrage do not violate the principles of democracy.

To put it abstractly, theories of representation differed in whether they took as the input the actual or ideal preferences, the latter being restricted by some normative requirements, such as they be other-regarding, consider
common good, etc. As Montesquieu (1995: 325; italics supplied) would say, political liberty does not consist of doing what one wants… liberty cannot be other but to be able to do what one ought to want and not to be obliged to do what one ought not want. Obviously, this distinction disappears if people naturally hold such ideal preferences. If they do not, the burden is placed on institutions, either to promote such preferences by educating citizens a common theme from Montesquieu to Mill or to treat such preferences in some privileged manner, by restricting su¤rage or weighting votes. As Beitz (1989: 35) observes, the latter solution defended by Mill is not unfair if those without such ideal preferences or without the conditions to develop
such preferences are willing to accept it. Moreover, while inegalitarian, such a system can be justifi…ed in universalistic terms if everyone can acquire such preferences or the conditions to acquire them.

Yet whatever one thinks of this logic, the …final outcome was that birth was replaced by wealth, aristocracy by oligarchy. Still only a select few were to rule in the best interest of all. The society was to be divided into the rich, the few, the rulers and the poor, the many, the ruled: which a Connecticut representative, Samuel Dana, thought was quite proper (Dunn S. 2004: 23).

The drafter of the French Constitution of 1795, Boissy d’Anglas, declared that We must be ruled by the best… a country governed by property-owners is within the social order, that which is dominated by non-property owners is in a state of nature (cited in Crook 1996: 46). The consensus in mid-nineteenth century Colombia was that We want enlightened democracy, a democracy in which intelligence and property direct the destinies of the people; we do not want a barbarian democracy in which the proletarianism and ignorance drown the seeds of happiness and bring the society to confusion and disorder(Gutiérrez Sanin 2003: 185). The right to make laws belongs to the most intelligent, to the aristocracy of knowledge, created by nature, a Peruvian constitutionalist, Bartolomé Herrera, declared in 1846 (Sobrevilla 2002: 196); the Peruvian theorist José María Pando maintained that a perpetual aristocracy … is an imperative necessity; the Chilean
Andrés Bello wanted rulers to constitute a body of wise men (un cuerpo de sabios)”; while the Spanish conservative thinker Donoso Cortés juxtaposed the sovereignty of the wise to sovereignty of the people (Gargarella 2005: 120). Still by 1867, Walter Bagehot (1963 [1867]: 277) would warn that It must be remembered that a political combination of the lower classes, as such and for their own objects, is an evil of the first magnitude; that a permanent combination of them would
make them (now that many of them have the su¤rage) supreme in the country; and that their supremacy, in the state they now
are, means the supremacy of ignorance over instruction and of numbers over knowledge.

It was perhaps not a full circle but a circle it was. And it left a legacy that gave rise to conflicts which in many countries lasted over a hundred years.

These new distinctions were soon perceived as evidence that democracy did not ful…lfil its own ideals. Neither the poor nor women thought that their best interests were being represented by propertied men. They would struggle for suffrage, and suffrage was a dangerous weapon.

5 Democracy and Property

In a society that is unequal, political equality, if it is effective, opens the possibility that the majority would by law equalize property or the bene…fits of its use. This is a central theme in the history of democracy, as alive and controversial today as it was at the inception of representative government.

Since, as distinct from liberty or happiness, property, the kind of property that can be used to generate incomes, always was and continues to be held by a minority, the right to protect property would have to hurl itself against the interest of majorities. Hence, a tension between democracy and property was predictable, and it was predicted.

To sketch the history of this tension, one must begin with the Levellers, who are identi…fied by Wootton (1993: 71) as the …first democrats who think in terms, not of participatory self government within a city-state, but of representative government within a nation-state. While they persistently and vehemently denied it, Levellers were feared by their opponents as wanting
to make everyone equal by redistributing land:15 in Harrington’s (1977: 460) words, By levelling, they who use the word seem to understand: when a people rising invades the lands and estates of the richer sort, and divides them equally among themselves. Some among them those calling themselves True Levellers or Diggers did set a commune on common land.

The demand for economic equality appeared during the French Revolution in Babeuf’s Plebeian Manifesto of 1795. Until then, while the revolutionary government confi…scated the lands of the Church and of the emigrant nobility, those were not redistributed to peasants but sold to rich commoners (Fontana 1993: 122). Babeuf did not want to equalize property, but to abolish it: we do not propose to divide up property, since no equal division would ever last. We propose to abolish private property altogether. Claiming that stomachs are equal, Babeuf wanted every man to place his product in a common pool
and receive from it an equal share. Hence, no one could take advantage of greater wealth or ability. He motivated his communist program by a moral principle, le bonheur commun, which must lead to the communauté, comfort for all, education for all, equality, liberty and happiness for all. (All citations are from Palmer 1964: 240-241.)

The demand for economic equality by the Babeuvists was derived from moral principles. Babeuf claimed that both legal and economic equality were only the natural outcome of the Enlightenment and both within the spirit of the French Revolution. Why should the fact or the postulate that all men are born equal justify political equality but not economic one? Why should
reasons be treated as equal but stomachs not? If logic does not dictate this distinction, one can suspect that only interests did. Even if the ultimate value is to be free from domination by another, the right to Natural Freedom, without being subjected to the Will or Authority of any other Man, does not economic compulsion to sell one’s services to another bind as much as the political subjugation to the command of another? Rousseau (1964: 154), at least, thought that no Citizen should be so opulent as to be able to buy another, and none so poor as to be constrained to sell himself.

But one can also think not on moral but on purely logical grounds that democracy, via legal equality, must lead to economic equality. Indeed, at some moment, legal and economic equality became connected by a syllogism: Universal suffrage, combined with majority rule, grants political power to the majority. And since the majority is always poor,16 it will con…fiscate
the riches. The syllogism was perhaps …first enunciated by Henry Ireton in the franchise debate at Putney in 1647: “It [universal male suffrage] may come to destroy property thus. You may have such men chosen, or at least the major part of them, as have no local or permanent interest. Why may not these men vote against all property?” (In Sharp 1998: 113-4). It was echoed
by a French conservative polemicist, J. Mallet du Pan, who insisted in 1796 that legal equality must lead to equality of wealth: Do you wish a republic of equals amid the inequalities which the public services, inheritances, marriage, industry and commerce have introduced into society? You will have to overthrow property(cited by Palmer 1964: 230).

Note that, contrary to frequent misquoting, of which I am guilty as well, Madison (Federalist #10) thought that this consequence applied to direct, but not to representative democracies. Having identifi…ed a pure Democracy as a system of direct rule, Madison continues that such Democracies have ever been spectacles of turbulence and contention; have ever been
found incompatible with personal security or the rights of property; and have in general been as short in their lives as they have been violent in their deaths
(italics supplied). Yet A Republic, by which I mean a Government in which the scheme of representation takes place, opens a different prospect and promises the cure for which we are seeking. Still, he seems to have been less sanguine some decades later: the danger to the holders of property can not be disguised, if they are undefended against a majority without property. Bodies of men are not less swayed by interest than individuals…. Hence, the
liability of the rights of property….
(Note written at some time between 1821 and 1829, in Ketcham 1986: 152).

Once coined, this syllogism has dominated the fears and the hopes attached to democracy ever since. Conservatives agreed with socialists that democracy, speci…fically universal suffrage, must undermine property. The self-serving nature of the convoluted arguments for restricting suffrage to the propertied became apparent. The Scottish philosopher James Mackintosh predicted in 1818 that if the laborious classes gain franchise, a permanent animosity between opinion and property must be the consequence (Cited in Collini, Winch and Burrow, 1983: 98). David Ricardo was prepared to extend suffrage only to that part of them which cannot be supposed to have an interest in overturning the right to property (In Collini, Winch and
Burrow, 1983: 107). Thomas Macaulay in the 1842 speech on the Chartists pictured the danger presented by universal suffrage in the following terms:
The essence of the Charter is universal suffrage. If you withhold that, it matters not very much what else you grant. If you
grant that, it matters not at all what else you withhold. If you grant that, the country is lost…. My …rm conviction is that, in our country, universal suffrage is incompatible, not only with this or that form of government, and with everything for the sake of which government exists; that it is incompatible with property and that it is consequently incompatible with civilization. (1900: 263)

Eight years later, from the other extreme of the political spectrum, Karl Marx expressed the same conviction that private property and universal suffrage are incompatible:

The classes whose social slavery the constitution is to perpetuate, proletariat, peasantry, petty bourgeoisie, it puts in possession of political power through universal suffrage. And from the class whose old social power it sanctions, the bourgeoisie, it withdraws the political guarantees of this power. It forces the political rule of the bourgeoisie into democratic conditions, which at every moment jeopardize the very foundations of bourgeois society. From the ones it demands that they should not go forward from political to social emancipation; from the others they should not go back from social to political restoration. (1952: 62).

According to Marx, democracy inevitably unchains the class struggle:
The poor use democracy to expropriate the riches; the rich are threatened and subvert democracy, by abdicating political power to the permanently organized armed forces. The combination of democracy and capitalism is thus an inherently unstable form of organization of society, only the political form of revolution of bourgeois society and not its conservative form of life (1934: 18), only a spasmodic, exceptional state of things … impossible as
the normal form of society
(1971: 198).

The fundamental contradiction of the Republican constitution identifi…ed by Marx would not materialize either if property ownership would expand spontaneously or if the dispossessed for some reasons abstained from using their political rights to con…scate property. On the other hand, Maier (1993: 127) notes, if the observer feared that social levelling would con-
tinue toward proletarianization, then the advance of democracy must appear an alarming trend. For this would suggest … that all democracy must in effect tend towards social democracy. That is, the advent of popular government and expanded electorate would ineluctably lead to programmes for further social equalization and redistribution on wealth.
Indeed, the idea
that democracy in the political realm must logically lead to social and economic equality became the cornerstone of Social Democracy. For Jean Jaures (1971: 71), The triumph of socialism will not be a break with the French Revolution but the ful…lfilment of the French Revolution in new economic conditions. Eduard Bernstein (1961) saw in socialism simply democracy brought to its logical conclusion. As Beitz (1989: xvi) observed, historically a main goal of democratic movements has been to seek redress in the political sphere for the effects of inequalities in the economy and society.
Socialists entered into elections with ultimate goals. The Hague Congress of the First International proclaimed that the organization of the proletariat into a political party is necessary to insure the victory of social revolution and its ultimate goal the abolition of classes.The …first Swedish socialist program specifi…ed that Social Democracy differs from other parties in that it aspires to completely transform the economic organization of the bourgeois society and bring about the social liberation of the working class….(Tingsten 1973: 118-9). Even the most reformist among socialists, Alexandre Millerand, admonished that whoever does not admit the necessary and progressive replacement of capitalist property by social property is not a socialist. (Cited in Ensor 1908: 51). Yet on the road to these ultimate goals, socialists saw numerous measures that would reduce social and economic inequalities. The Parti Socialiste Français, led by Jean Jaures, proclaimed at its Tour Congress of 1902 that The Socialist Party, rejecting the policy of all or nothing, has a program of reforms whose realization it pursues forthwith, and listed …fifty-four specifi…c measures (Ensor 1908: 345¤).

Swedish Social Democrats in 1897 demanded direct taxation, development of state and municipal productive activities, public credit, legislation concerning work conditions, old age, sickness, and accident insurance, as well as purely political rights (Tingsten 1973: 119-20).

The question that haunted social democrats was whether, as Hjalmar Branting posed it in 1886, the upper class [would] respect popular will even if it demanded the abolition of its privileges (cited in Tingsten 1973: 361). Were there limits to popular sovereignty, as exercised by electoral majorities? Would revolution not be necessary, as August Bebel feared in 1905, as a purely defensive measure, designed to safeguard the exercise of power legitimately acquired through the ballot? (cited in Schorske 1955: 43).

Yet there is a prior question which they did not consider. Can any political arrangement generate economic equality? Can equality be established by laws, even if the upper class would concede to the abolition of its privileges?

Or is some extent of economic inequality inevitable even if everyone would want to abolish it? Did egalitarian democrats fail or did they accomplish all that was within the reach?

6 By What Should We Be Surprised?

According to Dunn (2003: 22), democracy surprisingly turned from a revolutionary project into a conservative one Where the political force of the idea of democracy came from in this new epoch was its combination of formal social equality with a practical order founded on the protection and reproduction of an increasingly dynamic system of economic inequality….

No one at all in 1750 either did or could have seen democracy as a natural name or an apt institutional form for the effective
protection of productive wealth. But today we know better. In the teeth of ex ante perceived probability, that is exactly what
representative democracy has in the long run proved.

Should we share his surprise?

My argument has been that the sin was original. While, as Dunn (2005) emphasizes, in the second part of the eighteenth century democracy was a revolutionary idea, the revolution it offered was strictly political. Morally based arguments for redistribution or abolishment of property were marginal and ephemeral. In my reading, in its inception democracy was a project
simply blind to economic inequality, regardless how revolutionary it may have been politically. Moreover, by restricting suffrage, democracies replaced aristocracy by oligarchy.

Hence, I do not think that the surprise can be dated to 1750. In turn, viewed from the perspective of 1850, the coexistence of democracy with unequal distribution of property is hard to fathom. The syllogism according to which the poor would use their majority status to expropriate the rich was after all almost universally accepted. And it still makes logical sense today.

Just consider the favorite toy of political economists, the median voter model (Meltzer and Richards 1981): Each individual is characterized by an endowment of labor or capital and all individuals can be ranked from the poorest to the richest. Individuals vote on the rate of tax to be imposed on incomes generated by supplying these endowments to production. The revenues generated by this tax are either equally distributed to all individuals or spent to provide equally valued public goods, so that the tax rate uniquely determines the extent of redistribution. Once the tax rate is decided, individuals
maximize utility by deciding in a decentralized way how much of their endowments to supply. The median voter theorem asserts that there exists a unique majority rule equilibrium, this equilibrium is the choice of the voter with the median preference, and the voter with the median preference is the one with median income. And when the distribution of incomes is right-skewed, that is, if the median income is lower than the mean, as it is in all countries for which data exist, majority rule equilibrium is associated with a high degree of equality of post-…sc (tax and transfer) incomes, tempered only by the deadweight losses of redistribution. Moreover, the demand for social and economic equality persists. While elites see democracy in institutional terms, mass publics, at least in Eastern Europe and Latin America, conceive of it in terms of social and economic equality. In Chile, 59 percent of respondents expected that democracy would attenuate social inequalities (Alaminos 1991), while in Eastern Europe the proportion associating democracy with social equality ranged from 61 percent in Czechoslovakia to 88 percent in Bulgaria (Bruszt and Simon 1991). People do expect that democracy would breed social and economic equality. Hence,
the coexistence of democracy and inequality continues to be tense.

Yet income distribution appears to be amazingly stable over time. The strongest evidence, albeit for a relatively short period, comes from Li, Squire, and Zou (1997), who report that about 90 percent of total variance in the Gini coefficients is explained by the variation across countries, while few countries show any time trends. Longer time-series show that while income distribution became somewhat more equal in some democratic countries, redistribution was quite limited. These assertion are not contradictory: the main reason for equalization was that wars and major economic crises destroyed large fortunes and they could not be accumulated again because of progressive income tax. Earned incomes show almost no variation during the twentieth century. (For long-term dynamics of income distribution, see Piketty 2003 on France, Piketty and Saez 2003 on the United States, Saez and Veall 2003 on Canada, Banerjee and Piketty 2003 on India, Dell 2003 on Germany, and Atkinson 2002 on the United Kingdom.) It appears that there are no countries which equalized market incomes without some kind of cataclysm.

The cataclysms come in two kinds: (1) destruction of large property as a result of foreign occupation (Japanese in Korea, Soviet in Eastern Europe), revolution (Soviet Union), or war (France according to Piketty 2000), or (2) massive emigration of the poor (Norway, Sweden).

Since the issue is burning, explanations abound. Most assert that for a variety of reasons those without property, even if they constitute a vast majority in all known societies, either do not want to or cannot use their political rights to equalize property, incomes, or even opportunities. For reasons of space, I can only list the explanations of why the poor would not want to redistribute: (1) false consciousness due to a lack of understanding of the distinction between productive and non-productive property, (2) ideological domination due to the ownership of the media by the propertied, (3) difficulty of the poor to coordinate when they have some non-economic heterogeneous tastes, such as religion or race, (4) expectations that the poor would become rich, (5) the fact that taxes are palpable, while public spending is amorphous.

I am not taken by the idea that in general the poor would not want to lead better lives at the expense of the rich, but several arguments to the e¤ect that political rights are ineffective against private property make eminent sense.

Wealth holders enjoy disproportionate political influence, which they use to successfully defend themselves from redistribution (Benabou 2000).21 Nominally equal political rights do not seem to be enough to bar the privileged access of the rich to politics. Put differently, oblivion to economic differences is not sufficient to protect politics from the influence of money.

Yet this entire way of thinking confronts an awkward fact that many governments were elected with the support of the poor, wanted to equalize incomes, and tried to do so. Hence, to the extent to which they failed, it must have been for reasons other than not wanting or not trying. Here are some possible reasons:

(1) Redistributing productive property or even incomes is costly to the poor. Confronting the perspective of losing their property or not being able to enjoy its fruits, property owners save and invest less, thus reducing future wealth and future income of everyone. As Machiavelli observed, everybody is eager to acquire such things and to obtain property, provided that he be convinced that he will enjoy it when it has been acquired (Discourses on Livy. II.2, cited after Holmes 2003). Prospects of redistribution reduce investment. This structural dependence on capital (Przeworski and Wallerstein 1988) imposes a limit on redistribution even on those governments that want to equalize incomes. Hence, while some democratic governments do correct distributions of income generated by the unequal ownership of assets, equalizing assets ends up being a cataclysmic event, occurring only under exceptional circumstances.
(2) What are the assets that can be equalized in modern societies? Note that when the idea of equal property …rst appeared productive assets meant land. Land is relatively easy to redistribute. It is enough to take it from some and give it to others. Hence, agrarian reforms were frequent in history of the world: according to data collected by Thomas (2005), there were at
least 175 land reforms entailing redistribution between 1946 and 2000 alone. But today the distribution of land plays a relatively minor role in generating income inequality. In turn, other assets resist such a simple operation. Communists redistributed industrial capital by turning it into the hands of the state and announcing that the uninvested pro…ts would be equally distributed to households. This solution engendered several negative consequences that need not be discussed. Alternatively, one could redistribute titles to property in the form of shares. But this form of redistribution has problems
of its own.22 Finally, one could, and many countries did, equalize human capital by investing in education. But people exposed to the same educational system acquire very di¤erent income earning capacities as a function of their social and economic background. Moreover, since people are born with different talents and since the use of these talents is socially bene…ficial,
we would want to educate talented people more. In sum, redistributing productive assets seems to be di¢ cult for purely technological, not just political or economic, reasons.
(3) Asking How laws establish equality in a democracy? the title of Chapter 5 of Book 5 Montesquieu takes as the point of departure equality of land. Then he goes on, If, when the legislator makes such a division, he does not give laws to maintain it, he only makes a passing constitution; inequality will enter from the side the laws do not defend, and the republic
will be lost.
Therefore, although real equality would be the soul of the state, it is so difficult to establish that an extreme rigor in this respect is not always convenient. It is sufficient, he continues, to reduce differences to some point, after which, it is for particular laws to equalize, to put it this way, the inequalities, by the charges they impose on the rich and the relief they accord to the poor. (1995: 151-5)

Remember that Babeuf believed that redistribution of property would not solve the problem of inequality, “since no equal division would ever last.

Suppose productive assets had been equalized. But individuals have different and unobservable abilities to transform productive assets into incomes.

Moreover, they are subject to vicissitudes of luck. Assume that particular individuals (or projects they undertake) are subject to slightly different rates of return: some lose at the rate of -0.02 and some gain at the rate 0.02. After 25 years, the individual who generates a 2 percent return will be 2.7 times wealthier than the individual who loses 2 percent per year, and after 50 years (say from the age of 18 to 68) this multiple will be 7.4. Hence, even if productive assets were to be equalize, inequality would creep back in. (The classical statement of this argument is by Pareto 1897, investigated recently by Mookherjee and Ray 2003 as well as Benhabib and Bisin 2007).

7 Judging Democracy

Analyzing the Thatcher era, Dunn (2000: 147) observes that “the state at this point is more plausibly seen as a structure through which the minimally participant citizen body (those prepared to take the trouble to vote) select from the meagre options presented to them those they hope will best serve their several interests. In that selection, the meagreness of the range of options is always important and sometimes absolutely decisive.” The issue is to what extent these choices are tightly circumscribed because the logic of electoral competition pushes political parties to o¤er and pursue similar policies and to what extent there is just little else they could do. The question is important because it affects our political judgment of democracy (On political judgment, see Dunn 2000 and the Introduction to this volume). Suppose that economic inequality could be diminished below the levels prevailing in developed democracies without reducing future incomes and that it is not being
diminished only because of the institutional features of democracy, however one thinks about them. Obviously, judging this trade-o¤ would depend on other values we would have to give up opting for equality. But there is no such trade-off.

Some degree of economic inequality is just inevitable. Democracy is impotent against it, but so is every other conceivable political arrangement.

Think of Brazil: during the past two centuries it was a royal colony, an independent monarchy, an oligarchical republic, a populist military dictatorship, democracy with a weak presidency, a right-wing military dictatorship, and democracy with a strong presidency. Yet, to the best of our knowledge, income distribution did not budge. Even the communists, who were out to
uravnit everything, and who did equalize assets in the form of public ownership, had to tolerate the inequality arising from different talents and motivations. Indeed, it turns out that the average household/individual income inequality is almost exactly the same in democracies and in non-democracies at each level of per capita income.

The quest for equality in the economic and social realm has been perpetual in democracies. The original blinders that modern representative institutions placed on economic and social standing of citizens could not effectively cover the glaring inequality of their life conditions. At least since Babeuf, not to speak of Marx, limiting equality to the political realm always seemed “illogical.” Moreover, if the right always feared that effective political equality would threaten property, the left knew that equality limited to the political realm cannot be sustained in the face of economic and social inequalities.

“Extending democracy from the political to the social realm” was not just a call for social justice but for making democracy effective in the political realm itself. But this quest may have its limits and the knowledge of these limits is essential to judge democracy.

This is not to say that all democracies are the same. I am not arguing in support of Pareto’s “law,” according to which income distribution remains the same whatever the institutional framework and in spite of progressive taxation. Among contemporary democracies, the ratio incomes of the top to the bottom quintile, which is perhaps the most intuitive measure of inequality, ranges from about 33 in Brazil to less than 6 in Finland, Belgium, Spain, and South Korea. Hence, we can compare and judge the choices parties offer to voters, as well as policies of particular governments. Moreover, since conflicts over distribution of opportunities, employment, and consumption are the bread and butter of democratic politics, we must be vigilant. But even
the best governments operate under limits not of their making. The ratio of 6 is still very large: it means that in a country with per capita income of $15,000 (about average for these countries in 2002, counted in 1995 PPP dollars), a member of the top quintile would have the income of $27,000, while a member of the bottom quintile $4,500. Most survey respondents in Spain and South Korea see such inequality as excessive. Yet perhaps this is just the extent to which any political system can equalize assets or incomes.

My point, thus, is that perhaps Dunn, and we all, put too much burden on democracy.

8 References

Aguilar Rivera, José Antonio.
Alaminos, Antonio. 1991. Chile: transición politica y sociedad. Madrid:
Centro de Investigaciones Sociologicas.
Atkinson, A.B. 2002. Top Incomes in the United Kingdom over the Twentieth Century. Unpublished.
Banerjee, Abhijit and Thomas Piketty. 2003. Top Indian Incomes, 1922-2000. Unpublished.
Bagehot, Walter. 1963. The English Constitution. Ithaca, NY: Cornell
University Press.
Beitz, Charles R. 1989. Political Equality. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Bénabou, Roland. 2000. Unequal Societies: Income Distribution and the Social Contract. American Economic Review 90: 96-129.
Benhabib, Jess, and Alberto Bisin. 2007. “The distribution of wealth: Intergenerational transmission and redistribute policies.”Working paper, Department of Economics, New York University.
Bernstein, Eduard. 1961. Evolutionary Socialism. New York: Schocken.

Bolivar, Simon. 1969. Escritos politicos. Edited by Graciela Soriano,
Madrid: Alianza Editorial.
Bruszt, László, and János Simon. 1991. Political Culture, Political and Economical Orientations in Central and Eastern Europe during the Transition to Democracy. Manuscript. Budapest: Erasmus Foundation for Democracy.
Burda, Andrzej. 1990. Charakterystyka postanowie´n konstytucji PRLz 1952r. In Konstytucje Polski: Studja monogra…czne zdziejów polskiego
konstytucjonalizmu. Warszawa: Pa´nstwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe. Vol. 2, Pages 344-376.
Collier, Simon and William F. Sater. 1996. A History of Chile, 1808-1994. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Collini, Stefan, Donald Winch and John Burrow. 1983. That Noble Science of Politic

Democracy, Equality, and Redistribution

Adam Przeworski
Department of Politics
New York University
October 31, 2007

1 Introduction

Democratic citizens are not equal but only anonymous, indistinguishable by any traits they may possess. Democracy only places a veil over distinctions that exist in society. Even the one sense in which equality that can be said to characterize democracy equality before the law is derivative from anonymity: the law has to treat all citizens equally because they are
indistinguishable.

This norm of anonymity was circumvented in most early representative systems by an elaborate intellectual construction that justified? restrictions of suffrage. The argument held that the role of representatives is to promote the good of all, yet the intellectual capacity to recognize the common good and the moral qualities necessary to pursue it are not universal. These traits can be recognized by using some indicators, such as wealth, age, and gender.

Hence, relying on such indicators to restrict suffrage does not violate democratic norms. The logic of the argument is unimpeachable, but it is easy to suspect that it rationalized interests. This is the way it was perceived by those excluded, poor males and women, as they fought for political rights.

Yet even if political rights are universal, to ignore distinctions is to not to obliterate them. Democracy was a political revolution, but not an economic one. Should we be surprised that democracy turned out to be compatible with economic inequality? From its inception, representative institutions were haunted by the specter of the poor using their political rights to redistribute property. Should we be surprised that democracy did not undermine property, that the democratic revolution was never completed by being extended to the economic realm?

These three themes are developed below.

2 Aristocracy and Democracy

How did democracy reappear on the historical horizon and what did it mean to its proponents and opponents?

Since the emergence of modern democracy is the topic of Palmer’s (1959, 1964) monumental treatise, no more than a brief summary is necessary.

Palmer’s main point is that democracy was not a revolution against an existing system but a reaction against the increasing power of aristocracy. It was aristocracy that undermined monarchy; democracy outflanked it following in its footsteps. Palmer argues that (1) By the early eighteenth century, the aristocratic system of government was institutionalized in assemblies of
various forms, the participation in which was reserved to legally qualified? groups (constituted bodies) that always included hereditary nobility but in different places (countries, regions, principalities, cantons, city republics) also clergy, selected categories of burgers, and in Sweden even peasants. In all cases these bodies were politically dominated by hereditary nobility. (2) In the course of the century, these estate-based bodies increased their political influence. (3) At the same time, access to nobility, however it was de?nied in different places, became increasingly closed: nobility turned into
aristocracy. (4) The resulting aristocratic system suffered from several tensions, of which one was between birth and competence. (5) Politically crucial conflict was due to the exclusion from privilege of those who possessed all the qualifi?cations to participate wealth, talent, bearing except for birth. (6) Democracy emerged as a demand for access to these bodies, not as a movement against monarchy.

Hence, by the end of the eighteenth century, democracy was a slogan directed against legal recognition of inherited distinctions of social status.

Democrats were those who agitated against aristocrats or aristocracy.. As Dunn (2003: 10) observes, democracy was a reaction, above all, not to monarchy, let alone tyranny, but to another relatively concrete social category, initially all too well entrenched, but no longer plausibly aligned with social, economic, or even political or military, functions the nobility or aristocracy…. Democrat was a label in and for political combat; and what that combat was directed against was aristocrats, or at the very least aristocracy.?2 Thus, in 1794 a young Englishman described himself as being of that odious class of men called democrats because he disapproved of hereditary distinctions and privileged orders of every species (Palmer 1964: 22).

Could any further proof be required of the republican complexion of this system, wrote Madison in The Federalist # 39, the most decisive might be found in its absolute prohibition of titles of nobility. In France, the Constituent Assembly decided that aristocratic privilege was in conflict with the very principle of popular sovereignty (Fontana 1993: 119). The Batavian (Dutch) Republic established in 1796 required voters to swear an oath to the belief that all hereditary offices and dignities were illegal (Palmer 1964: 195). In Chile, General O’Higgins, the ?first Director of the State, abolished
in 1818 all outward and visible signs of aristocracy (Collier and Sater 1006: 42).

Here is a puzzle. While democrats fought against aristocracy, either as a system of government (the original meaning of the word) or as a legal status (nobility), this struggle did not have to result in abolishing other distinctions. One distinction could have been replaced by another. The flagrant case is the Polish Constitution of 3 May 1791, which was directed against
aristocrats de?fined as large landowners, magnates, under the slogan of equality for the gentry at large (szlachta, which constituted about 10 percent of the population), while preserving a legal distinction of the latter. More generally, social traits that could serve as basis for legal distinctions were many: property owners and laborers, burgers and peasants, inhabitants of different localities, clergy and army, whites and blacks. Yet democrats turned against other distinctions. All the privileges, Sieyes (1979 [1788]: 3) declared, are thus by the nature of things unjust, despicable and contradictory to the supreme goal of all political society. From aristocracy, the enemy became any kind of particularity (Rosanvallon 2004: 37 and throughout). Thus, in far away Brazil, the four mulattoes who were hanged and quartered after the failure of the Citade da Bahia Republicana in 1798 were accused of desiring the imaginary advantages of a Democratic Republic in which all should be equal … without difference of color or condition(Palmer 1964: 513). The French Revolution emancipated Protestants and Jews and freed slaves, not only Catholic peasants.

Rosanvallon (2004: 121) claims that The imperative of equality, required to make everyone a subject of law and a full citizen, implies in effect considering men stripped of their particularistic determinants. All their differences and all their distinctions should be placed at a distance…. Yet where did the imperative of equality come from? Thinking in the rational choice terms of modern political science, one would suspect that democrats instrumentally turned against other social distinctions just to mobilize the masses against aristocracy: to gain support against aristocracy. Finer (1934: 85), for example, accuses Montesquieu of deliberately juxtaposing the Citizen to all the powers that be, either the King or the aristocracy: it was a convenient, a striking and useful antithesis; nothing could be better calculated to win the support of every man. There are facts that support this hypothesis: Tadeusz Kosciuszko in Poland made vague promises to peasants to induce them join the anti-Russian insurrection in 1794; the members of the French Convention flagrantly played up to the gallery ?filled by the ordinary people of Paris; Simon Bolivar made interracial appeals to recruit for the war against Spain.

Yet it is also easy to believe that democrats truly believed that all men are equal, as the Declaration of Independence declared or that men are born equal, as the Declaration of the Rights of Man would have it. The idea of innate equality certainly preceded the actual political conflicts. It could be found already in Locke’s Second Treatise (1690) as the principle that equal Right that every Man hath, to his Natural Freedom, without being subjected to the Will or Authority of any other Man. We do not have a theory of action in which people are moved by logic, in which they do things because they cannot tolerate logical contradictions. Yet if one is willing to accept that people can be moved by ideas, democrats would have turned against other distinctions by the sheer logic of their ideology: Aristocrats are not distinct because all men are born equal; because all men are born equal, they cannot be treated differently. Abolishing other distinctions would then be a logical
outcome of the struggle against aristocracy.

The fact is that democrats turned against all distinctions. The only attribute of democratic subjects is that they have none as such. The democratic citizen is simply without qualities.6 Not equal, not homogeneous, just anonymous. Even the one sense in which equality does apply as a democratic norm, namely, before the law, is just a consequence of the principle that democratic citizens cannot be distinguished in any way. As Rousseau (1964: 129) said, the sovereign [the people united] knows only the body of the nation and does not distinguish any of those who compose it. Since citizens are indistinguishable, there is nothing by which law could possibly distinguish them. The democratic citizen is simply an individual outside society. One can say an aristocrat, a wealthy person, and male, but not an aristocratic citizen, a wealthy citizen, or a male citizen. As Sieyes (1979: 183) put it, On doit concevoir les nations sur terre comme
des individues hors de lien social.

3 Democracy and Equality

In spite of its egalitarian pedigree, I am about to argue, there is no sense in which equality could or does characterize democracy. One should not let oneself be trapped by words, Pasquino (1998: 149-150) warns, the society
without qualities
is not a society of equals; it is simply a society in which privileges do not have a juridical-institutional status or recognition.
In a scathing critique of bourgeois rights, Marx (1844: no page) characterized
this duality as follows:

The state abolishes, in its own way, distinctions of birth, social rank, education, occupation, when it declares that birth, social rank, education, occupation, are non-political distinctions, when it proclaims, without regard to these distinctions, that every member of the nation is an equal participant in national sovereignty…. Nevertheless the state allows private property, education, occupation to act in their way -i.e., as private property, as education, as occupation, and to exert the influence of their special nature.

Why then political emancipation is not a form of human emancipation, as Marx would have put it? Speci?cally, in what ways is the veil over distinctions compatible with various kinds of inequality?

Consider the different meanings in which equalityappeared in democratic ideology. Why are or would be people equal? They could be because God or nature made them so, because society makes them so, or because the law makes them so. Equality can be innate or generated by spontaneous social transformations, but it can also be instituted by law or by the use of laws.

Democratic equality may thus be a reflection of equality pre-existing elsewhere or it may be imposed by laws.

To return to the Declarations one last time, the point of departure of democrats was innate equality of human beings. Democratic equality is but a reflection of a pre-existing, natural, equality. Yet the implications of a pre-existing equality are indeterminate. As Schmitt (1993: 364) observed, From the fact that all men are men it is not possible to deduce anything specifi?c either about morality or about religion or about politics or about economics.

Even if people were born equal, they may distinguish themselves by their merits and their merits may be recognized by others. More, to maintain order, some people must at each moment exercise authority over others. As Kelsen (1988 [1929]: 17) put it, From the idea that we are all equal, ideally equal, one can deduce that no one should command another. But experience
teaches that if we want to remain equal in reality, it is necessary on the contrary that we let ourselves be commanded.

Moreover, even if all human beings are born only as such, society generates differences among them. Indeed, if their parents are unequal, they become unequal at the moment they are born. To make them equal again, a recourse to laws is necessary. Montesquieu (1995: 261) would thus observe that In the state of nature, men are born equal but they do not know how to remain so. Society makes them lose equality and they do not return to be equal other than by laws.

Yet must society make people unequal? Rosanvallon (1995: 149) documents that when the term democracy came into widespread usage in France after 1814, it connoted modern egalitarian society, not the political regimes associated with the classical Greek or Roman republics, what Tocqueville would refer to as equality of conditions. The tendency toward social equality was inevitable. Taking a theme of Marquis d’Argenson (1764), Tocqueville (1961, vol I: 41) observed that The gradual development of equality of conditions … is universal, it is durable, it escapes human intervention every day;
every event, like every man, furthers its development.
J.S. Mill noted the same in 1859: There is confessedly a strong tendency in the modern world towards a democratic constitution of society, accompanied or not by popular political institutions. Note that while Tocqueville saw political equality in the United States as a natural consequence of the equality of conditions, for Mill the fact of social equality did not have unique political consequences.

Whether modern societies must become more equal is a complex question.

What matters here is that not everyone was willing to rely on the spontaneous evolution of society to generate political equality. Robespierre thought that Equality of wealth is a chimera. (Palmer 1964: 109). Madison (Federalist #10) listed all kinds of social differences and gradations, assuming they were there to stay. Most democrats believed against Tocqueville that citizenship creates equality, rather than equals become citizens. Pasquino (1998: 109) summarizes this belief: Citizens are not simply equal before the law, in the sense in which the law does not recognize either special rights or privileges,
but they become equal by the grace of law and by law itself.

Democrats adhered to what Beitz (1989: 4) calls a simple conception of political equality, namely, the requirement that democratic institutions should provide citizens with equal procedural opportunities to influence political decisions (or, more briefly, with equal power over outcomes). Criticizing this notion, he points out that equality of the abstract leverage that procedures provide to each participant does not imply equality of the actual influence over the outcomes: the latter depends also on the distribution of the preferences and of the enabling resources. This disjunction between formal and effective political equality was a central concern in the United States and continues to be debated today. The social palliative to this divergence between formal and real influence is pluralism. The political answer, at least for Madison, was large districts.

As Mill would remark several decades later, without decent wages and universal reading, no government of public opinion is possible. Education was one instrument that would equip people to exercise their citizenship rights. Several early constitutions (of the Italian republics between 1796 and 1799, the Cádiz Constitutions of 1812) established systems of universal and free, although not compulsory, education. In the meantime, most solved the problem by restricting political rights to those who were in condition to exercise them. Yet when suffrage became universal and democracy found roots in
poorer countries, the problem reappeared with a vengeance: masses of people acquired equal procedural opportunities without enjoying the conditions necessary to exploit them. Citizenship without the conditions to exercise it is a monster that haunts contemporary democracies. The absence of the effective capacity to exercise formal political rights remains at the heart of
criticisms of the really existing democracy. To return to Marx, can people be politically equal if they are socially unequal?

But political equality is vulnerable not just to social inequality but also to speci?fically political distinctions. Democracy, according to Schmitt (1993: 372), is the identity of the dominating and the dominated, of the government and the governed, of he who commands and he who obeys. But the issue is whether the very faculty of governing does not create a distinction, a
political class. Political aristocracy was seen as much of a danger as social aristocracy. The Anti-Federalists feared that if the rulers were other than the ruled, Corruption and tyranny would be rampant as they have always been when those who exercised power felt little connection with the people.

This would be true, moreover, for elected representatives, as well as for kings and nobles and bishops… (Ketcham 1986: 18). Hence, democrats were preoccupied with duration of terms, as short as six months in New Jersey at one time, term limits, restrictions on representatives to determine their own salaries, and censuring procedures.

Yet these are palliatives. The distinction between the representatives and the represented is inherent in the representative system: parliaments seat representatives, not the people. And the very method of choosing representatives through elections, rather than by lot, is based on the belief that all people are not equally quali?fied to rule. Elections, Manin (1997) argues, are based on the assumption that the qualities necessary to govern are not universally shared and that people want to be governed by their betters. These qualities need not be associated with distinctions of birth, so that elections are not aristocratic in the eighteenth century sense. But elections are a method for selecting one’s betters and, as Manin amply documents, they are and were seen as a way of recognizing a natural aristocracy of talent, reason, or whatever else voters would see as the index of the ability to govern.

Moreover, to be represented people must be organized and organization demands a permanent apparatus, a salaried bureaucracy, a propaganda machine. Hence, Michels (1962: 270) bemoaned, some militants become parliamentarians, party bureaucrats, newspaper editors, managers of the party’s insurance companies, directors of the party’s funeral parlors, and even Parteibudiger party bar keepers. As a disillusioned French communist would write many years later, The working class is lost in administering
its imaginary bastions. Comrades disguised as notables occupy themselves with municipal garbage dumps and school cafeterias. Or are these notables disguised as comrades? I no longer know(Konopnicki 1979: 53).

To summarize, the idea that political equality reflects some pre-existing state, either of nature or society, is untenable on both logical and empirical grounds. Logically, equality pre-existing in other realms does not imply political equality.

Empirically, even if all human beings were born equal, they become unequal in society, and even if societies experienced an inevitable tendency toward equality, the existing inequalities were and are sufficient to call for political remedies. In turn, political equality instituted by law is effectively undermined by social inequality. Political equality is equality in the eyes of a third party, the state, but not in the direct relation between any two persons. In no meaning then is equality the correct way to characterize democracy. If the founders used the languages of equality, it was to justify something else, better described as anonymity, generality, or oblivion to social distinctions.

4 Do Suffrage Restrictions Violate Democratic Ideology?

Yet there is one fact that appears to undermine anonymity: restrictions of suffrage. Indeed, the French Declaration qualified? its recognition of equality in the sentence that immediately followed: Men are born equal and remain free and equal in rights. Social distinctions may be founded only upon the general good. While some early constitutions made male suffrage nearly universal, during most of the nineteenth century the right to vote and the right to be elected was con?fined to adult men who owned property, earned some amount of income, or paid some amount of taxes.

The prevalence of suffrage censitaire may appear to contradict the norm of suppressing all distinctions in society and to be incompatible with the principle of political equality. Yet, even if the arguments were convoluted, franchise restrictions were not portrayed as such by their proponents.

Consider ?first the justi?cation by Montesquieu (1995: 155), who starts from the principle that All inequality under democracy should be derived from the nature of democracy and from the very principle of democracy. His example is that people who must continually work to live are not prepared for public office or would neglect their functions. As barristers of Paris put
it on the eve of the Revolution, Whatever respect one might wish to show for the rights of humanity in general, there is no denying the existence of a class of men who, by virtue of their education and the type of work to which their poverty had condemned them, is … incapable at the moment of participating fully in public affairs(cited in Crook 1996: 13). In such cases, Montesquieu goes on, equality among citizens can be lifted in a democracy for the good of democracy. But it is only apparent equality which is lifted…. The generic argument, to be found in slightly different versions, is that: (1) Representation is acting in the best interest of all. (2) To determine the best interest of all one needs reason. (3) Reason has sociological determinants: not having to work for a living (disinterest), or not being employed or otherwise dependent on others (independence). As a Chilean statesman put it in 1865, to exercise political rights it is necessary to have the intelligence to recognize the truth and the good, the will to want it, and the freedom to execute it. (A speech by Senador Abdón Cifuentes, cited in Maza Valenzuela 1995: 153). In turn, the claim that only apparent equality is being violated was built in three steps: (1) Acting in the best common interest considers everyone equally, so that everyone is equally represented. (2) The only quality that is being distinguished is the capacity to recognize the common good. (3) No one is barred from acquiring this quality, so that suffrage is potentially open to all.

The last two points are crucial. Legal distinctions of social status are valid only as indicators of the ability to govern and there are no barriers of any kind to prevent people from acquiring this ability and being relevantly indicated.

The Polish Constitution of 3 May 1791 illuminates the distinction between the democratic regime censitaire and non-democratic regime of legal distinctions. The Constitution asserts in Paragraph VI that deputies to the local parliaments … should be considered as representatives of the entire nation(italics in the original). Yet to become a deputy to the local parliaments (sejmiki, which, in turn elect deputies to the national legislature, the sejm) one had to be a member of a legally de?fined group, the gentry (szlachta). In turn, only members of the hereditary gentry could own land entitling to political rights. Hence, this was not a regime censitaire in the sense defi?ned above: (1) it barred access to politics to everyone who was not a member of a legally recognized group, the landed gentry, and (2) it barred access to the landed gentry.

In fact, the Polish justi?cation for privileging gentry was not reason but
Respect for the memory of our forefathers as founders of free government….
(Article II). Simon Bolivar used the same principle in 1819 when he offered positions of hereditary senators to the liberators of Venezuela, … to whom the Republic owns its existence(1969: 109). His celebrated speech, known
as the Discurso de Angostura, merits attention because its combination of appeals to reason with an acceptance of inequality became the hallmark of anti-democratic postures in Spanish America. Bolivar observed that most people do not know their true interests and went on to argue that Everything cannot be left to the adventure of elections: the People errs easily…. His solution was the institution of a hereditary Senate: future Senators Would learn the arts, sciences, and letters which adorn the spirit of a public man; from infancy would know to what Providence destined them…. And he had the gumption to claim that The creation of a hereditary Senate would in no way violate political equality.

Restrictions of political rights based on religion were also couched in a universalistic language, but the appeal was not to reason but to common values. From Rousseau and Kant to J.S. Mill, everyone believed that a polity can function only if it is based on common interests, norms, or values. In Latin America (indeed, also in the Spanish Constitution of 1812), the cement
holding societies together was to be Catholicism: of the 103 Latin American constitutions studied by Loveman (1993: 371), 83 proclaimed Catholicism as the official religion and 55 prohibited worship of other religions. While many arguments for restricting political rights to Catholics were openly directed against the principle of popular sovereignty it is not for people to change what God willed quite a few were pragmatic. For example, the Mexican thinker Lucas Alamán maintained in 1853 that Catholic religion deserves support by the state, even if we do not consider it as divine, because it constitutes the only common tie that connects all Mexicans, when all others are broken(cited after Gargarella 2005: 93, who provides other examples).

Restrictions on female suffrage present the most difficult issue. While early proponents of female suffrage observed that reason is not distributed along gender lines after all, some rulers had been queens (Sieyes according to Pasquino 1998: 71) the main argument against giving the right to vote to women was that, like children, they were not independent, had no will of their own. Women were already represented by the males in their households and their interests were to be represented through a tutelary, rather than an electoral, connection. Thus the justifying criterion was dependence, not sex.

Indeed, when a study in England in the 1880s discovered that almost one half of adult women lived in households in which there was no adult male, this justi?fication collapsed, and only pure prejudice retarded extending suffrage to women.

Yet why were women not independent in the same way as some men were? If women could not own property, they were legally barred from qualifying for suffrage, so this would violate the democratic ideology. But where they could and did own property in their own name, why would property ownership not be a sufficient indicator? Condorcet (1986 [1788]: 293), who defended property qualifi?cations, thought it should be: The reason for which it is believed that they [women] should be excluded from public function, reasons that albeit are easy to destroy, cannot be a motive for depriving them of a right which would be so simple to exercise [voting], and which men have not because of their sex, but because of their quality of being reasonable and sensible, which they have in common with women. And Chilean suffragettes claimed that Wives and mothers, widows and daughters, we all have time and money to devote to the happiness of Chile. (An article in El Eco, 3 August 1865, cited in Maza Valenzuela 1995: 156).

Since this is an issue about which it is easy to fall into anachronisms, let me process it through an example. Suppose that it is in the best interest of each and all people to evacuate a coastal town if a hurricane is impending and not to evacuate it if the danger is remote. A correct decision is good for everyone: all men, women, and children. The correct decision can be
reached only by people who can interpret weather forecasts. This excludes children, so that the decision should be made by parents in the best interest of children. I suspect that with some quibbles about where to draw the age line most people today would accept this reasoning: all contemporary democratic constitutions do. But why should only men participate in making
this decision? If the reason is that women are barred from taking meteorology courses in school, then we are back to the 1791 Poland. But suppose they do take such courses. Now the argument must be that even if they had the same capacity to exercise reason, women would always follow the views of their male protectors, independently of their own opinions. This is then
another sociological assumption, in addition to those that tied reason to property, income, or education.

Now, Schumpeter (1942: 244) argued that if any distinction is accepted, then the principle of making such distinctions must be as well: The salient point is that, given appropriate views on those and similar subjects, disquali?cations on ground of economic status, religion and sex will enter into the same class with disquali?cations which all of us consider compatible with
democracy.
Yet each distinction is based on a speci?c assumption for example, that 12-year olds are not prepared to vote tying it to the capacity to exercise reason. Obviously, today we would and do reject most such assumptions, although not those based on age or legally certi?fied sanity. Moreover, as we will see below, some such assumptions were driven by
only thinly veiled self-interest. But if these assumptions are accepted, then restrictions of suffrage do not violate the principles of democracy.

To put it abstractly, theories of representation differed in whether they took as the input the actual or ideal preferences, the latter being restricted by some normative requirements, such as they be other-regarding, consider
common good, etc. As Montesquieu (1995: 325; italics supplied) would say, political liberty does not consist of doing what one wants… liberty cannot be other but to be able to do what one ought to want and not to be obliged to do what one ought not want. Obviously, this distinction disappears if people naturally hold such ideal preferences. If they do not, the burden is placed on institutions, either to promote such preferences by educating citizens a common theme from Montesquieu to Mill or to treat such preferences in some privileged manner, by restricting su¤rage or weighting votes. As Beitz (1989: 35) observes, the latter solution defended by Mill is not unfair if those without such ideal preferences or without the conditions to develop
such preferences are willing to accept it. Moreover, while inegalitarian, such a system can be justifi?ed in universalistic terms if everyone can acquire such preferences or the conditions to acquire them.

Yet whatever one thinks of this logic, the ?final outcome was that birth was replaced by wealth, aristocracy by oligarchy. Still only a select few were to rule in the best interest of all. The society was to be divided into the rich, the few, the rulers and the poor, the many, the ruled: which a Connecticut representative, Samuel Dana, thought was quite proper (Dunn S. 2004: 23).

The drafter of the French Constitution of 1795, Boissy d’Anglas, declared that We must be ruled by the best… a country governed by property-owners is within the social order, that which is dominated by non-property owners is in a state of nature (cited in Crook 1996: 46). The consensus in mid-nineteenth century Colombia was that We want enlightened democracy, a democracy in which intelligence and property direct the destinies of the people; we do not want a barbarian democracy in which the proletarianism and ignorance drown the seeds of happiness and bring the society to confusion and disorder(Gutiérrez Sanin 2003: 185). The right to make laws belongs to the most intelligent, to the aristocracy of knowledge, created by nature, a Peruvian constitutionalist, Bartolomé Herrera, declared in 1846 (Sobrevilla 2002: 196); the Peruvian theorist José María Pando maintained that a perpetual aristocracy … is an imperative necessity; the Chilean
Andrés Bello wanted rulers to constitute a body of wise men (un cuerpo de sabios)?; while the Spanish conservative thinker Donoso Cortés juxtaposed the sovereignty of the wise to sovereignty of the people (Gargarella 2005: 120). Still by 1867, Walter Bagehot (1963 [1867]: 277) would warn that It must be remembered that a political combination of the lower classes, as such and for their own objects, is an evil of the first magnitude; that a permanent combination of them would
make them (now that many of them have the su¤rage) supreme in the country; and that their supremacy, in the state they now
are, means the supremacy of ignorance over instruction and of numbers over knowledge.

It was perhaps not a full circle but a circle it was. And it left a legacy that gave rise to conflicts which in many countries lasted over a hundred years.

These new distinctions were soon perceived as evidence that democracy did not ful?lfil its own ideals. Neither the poor nor women thought that their best interests were being represented by propertied men. They would struggle for suffrage, and suffrage was a dangerous weapon.

5 Democracy and Property

In a society that is unequal, political equality, if it is effective, opens the possibility that the majority would by law equalize property or the bene?fits of its use. This is a central theme in the history of democracy, as alive and controversial today as it was at the inception of representative government.

Since, as distinct from liberty or happiness, property, the kind of property that can be used to generate incomes, always was and continues to be held by a minority, the right to protect property would have to hurl itself against the interest of majorities. Hence, a tension between democracy and property was predictable, and it was predicted.

To sketch the history of this tension, one must begin with the Levellers, who are identi?fied by Wootton (1993: 71) as the ?first democrats who think in terms, not of participatory self government within a city-state, but of representative government within a nation-state. While they persistently and vehemently denied it, Levellers were feared by their opponents as wanting
to make everyone equal by redistributing land:15 in Harrington’s (1977: 460) words, By levelling, they who use the word seem to understand: when a people rising invades the lands and estates of the richer sort, and divides them equally among themselves. Some among them those calling themselves True Levellers or Diggers did set a commune on common land.

The demand for economic equality appeared during the French Revolution in Babeuf’s Plebeian Manifesto of 1795. Until then, while the revolutionary government confi?scated the lands of the Church and of the emigrant nobility, those were not redistributed to peasants but sold to rich commoners (Fontana 1993: 122). Babeuf did not want to equalize property, but to abolish it: we do not propose to divide up property, since no equal division would ever last. We propose to abolish private property altogether. Claiming that stomachs are equal, Babeuf wanted every man to place his product in a common pool
and receive from it an equal share. Hence, no one could take advantage of greater wealth or ability. He motivated his communist program by a moral principle, le bonheur commun, which must lead to the communauté, comfort for all, education for all, equality, liberty and happiness for all. (All citations are from Palmer 1964: 240-241.)

The demand for economic equality by the Babeuvists was derived from moral principles. Babeuf claimed that both legal and economic equality were only the natural outcome of the Enlightenment and both within the spirit of the French Revolution. Why should the fact or the postulate that all men are born equal justify political equality but not economic one? Why should
reasons be treated as equal but stomachs not? If logic does not dictate this distinction, one can suspect that only interests did. Even if the ultimate value is to be free from domination by another, the right to Natural Freedom, without being subjected to the Will or Authority of any other Man, does not economic compulsion to sell one’s services to another bind as much as the political subjugation to the command of another? Rousseau (1964: 154), at least, thought that no Citizen should be so opulent as to be able to buy another, and none so poor as to be constrained to sell himself.

But one can also think not on moral but on purely logical grounds that democracy, via legal equality, must lead to economic equality. Indeed, at some moment, legal and economic equality became connected by a syllogism: Universal suffrage, combined with majority rule, grants political power to the majority. And since the majority is always poor,16 it will con?fiscate
the riches. The syllogism was perhaps ?first enunciated by Henry Ireton in the franchise debate at Putney in 1647: “It [universal male suffrage] may come to destroy property thus. You may have such men chosen, or at least the major part of them, as have no local or permanent interest. Why may not these men vote against all property?” (In Sharp 1998: 113-4). It was echoed
by a French conservative polemicist, J. Mallet du Pan, who insisted in 1796 that legal equality must lead to equality of wealth: Do you wish a republic of equals amid the inequalities which the public services, inheritances, marriage, industry and commerce have introduced into society? You will have to overthrow property(cited by Palmer 1964: 230).

Note that, contrary to frequent misquoting, of which I am guilty as well, Madison (Federalist #10) thought that this consequence applied to direct, but not to representative democracies. Having identifi?ed a pure Democracy as a system of direct rule, Madison continues that such Democracies have ever been spectacles of turbulence and contention; have ever been
found incompatible with personal security or the rights of property; and have in general been as short in their lives as they have been violent in their deaths
(italics supplied). Yet A Republic, by which I mean a Government in which the scheme of representation takes place, opens a different prospect and promises the cure for which we are seeking. Still, he seems to have been less sanguine some decades later: the danger to the holders of property can not be disguised, if they are undefended against a majority without property. Bodies of men are not less swayed by interest than individuals…. Hence, the
liability of the rights of property….
(Note written at some time between 1821 and 1829, in Ketcham 1986: 152).

Once coined, this syllogism has dominated the fears and the hopes attached to democracy ever since. Conservatives agreed with socialists that democracy, speci?fically universal suffrage, must undermine property. The self-serving nature of the convoluted arguments for restricting suffrage to the propertied became apparent. The Scottish philosopher James Mackintosh predicted in 1818 that if the laborious classes gain franchise, a permanent animosity between opinion and property must be the consequence (Cited in Collini, Winch and Burrow, 1983: 98). David Ricardo was prepared to extend suffrage only to that part of them which cannot be supposed to have an interest in overturning the right to property (In Collini, Winch and
Burrow, 1983: 107). Thomas Macaulay in the 1842 speech on the Chartists pictured the danger presented by universal suffrage in the following terms:
The essence of the Charter is universal suffrage. If you withhold that, it matters not very much what else you grant. If you
grant that, it matters not at all what else you withhold. If you grant that, the country is lost…. My ?rm conviction is that, in our country, universal suffrage is incompatible, not only with this or that form of government, and with everything for the sake of which government exists; that it is incompatible with property and that it is consequently incompatible with civilization. (1900: 263)

Eight years later, from the other extreme of the political spectrum, Karl Marx expressed the same conviction that private property and universal suffrage are incompatible:

The classes whose social slavery the constitution is to perpetuate, proletariat, peasantry, petty bourgeoisie, it puts in possession of political power through universal suffrage. And from the class whose old social power it sanctions, the bourgeoisie, it withdraws the political guarantees of this power. It forces the political rule of the bourgeoisie into democratic conditions, which at every moment jeopardize the very foundations of bourgeois society. From the ones it demands that they should not go forward from political to social emancipation; from the others they should not go back from social to political restoration. (1952: 62).

According to Marx, democracy inevitably unchains the class struggle:
The poor use democracy to expropriate the riches; the rich are threatened and subvert democracy, by abdicating political power to the permanently organized armed forces. The combination of democracy and capitalism is thus an inherently unstable form of organization of society, only the political form of revolution of bourgeois society and not its conservative form of life (1934: 18), only a spasmodic, exceptional state of things … impossible as
the normal form of society
(1971: 198).

The fundamental contradiction of the Republican constitution identifi?ed by Marx would not materialize either if property ownership would expand spontaneously or if the dispossessed for some reasons abstained from using their political rights to con?scate property. On the other hand, Maier (1993: 127) notes, if the observer feared that social levelling would con-
tinue toward proletarianization, then the advance of democracy must appear an alarming trend. For this would suggest … that all democracy must in effect tend towards social democracy. That is, the advent of popular government and expanded electorate would ineluctably lead to programmes for further social equalization and redistribution on wealth.
Indeed, the idea
that democracy in the political realm must logically lead to social and economic equality became the cornerstone of Social Democracy. For Jean Jaures (1971: 71), The triumph of socialism will not be a break with the French Revolution but the ful?lfilment of the French Revolution in new economic conditions. Eduard Bernstein (1961) saw in socialism simply democracy brought to its logical conclusion. As Beitz (1989: xvi) observed, historically a main goal of democratic movements has been to seek redress in the political sphere for the effects of inequalities in the economy and society.
Socialists entered into elections with ultimate goals. The Hague Congress of the First International proclaimed that the organization of the proletariat into a political party is necessary to insure the victory of social revolution and its ultimate goal the abolition of classes.The ?first Swedish socialist program specifi?ed that Social Democracy differs from other parties in that it aspires to completely transform the economic organization of the bourgeois society and bring about the social liberation of the working class….(Tingsten 1973: 118-9). Even the most reformist among socialists, Alexandre Millerand, admonished that whoever does not admit the necessary and progressive replacement of capitalist property by social property is not a socialist. (Cited in Ensor 1908: 51). Yet on the road to these ultimate goals, socialists saw numerous measures that would reduce social and economic inequalities. The Parti Socialiste Français, led by Jean Jaures, proclaimed at its Tour Congress of 1902 that The Socialist Party, rejecting the policy of all or nothing, has a program of reforms whose realization it pursues forthwith, and listed ?fifty-four specifi?c measures (Ensor 1908: 345¤).

Swedish Social Democrats in 1897 demanded direct taxation, development of state and municipal productive activities, public credit, legislation concerning work conditions, old age, sickness, and accident insurance, as well as purely political rights (Tingsten 1973: 119-20).

The question that haunted social democrats was whether, as Hjalmar Branting posed it in 1886, the upper class [would] respect popular will even if it demanded the abolition of its privileges (cited in Tingsten 1973: 361). Were there limits to popular sovereignty, as exercised by electoral majorities? Would revolution not be necessary, as August Bebel feared in 1905, as a purely defensive measure, designed to safeguard the exercise of power legitimately acquired through the ballot? (cited in Schorske 1955: 43).

Yet there is a prior question which they did not consider. Can any political arrangement generate economic equality? Can equality be established by laws, even if the upper class would concede to the abolition of its privileges?

Or is some extent of economic inequality inevitable even if everyone would want to abolish it? Did egalitarian democrats fail or did they accomplish all that was within the reach?

6 By What Should We Be Surprised?

According to Dunn (2003: 22), democracy surprisingly turned from a revolutionary project into a conservative one Where the political force of the idea of democracy came from in this new epoch was its combination of formal social equality with a practical order founded on the protection and reproduction of an increasingly dynamic system of economic inequality….

No one at all in 1750 either did or could have seen democracy as a natural name or an apt institutional form for the effective
protection of productive wealth. But today we know better. In the teeth of ex ante perceived probability, that is exactly what
representative democracy has in the long run proved.

Should we share his surprise?

My argument has been that the sin was original. While, as Dunn (2005) emphasizes, in the second part of the eighteenth century democracy was a revolutionary idea, the revolution it offered was strictly political. Morally based arguments for redistribution or abolishment of property were marginal and ephemeral. In my reading, in its inception democracy was a project
simply blind to economic inequality, regardless how revolutionary it may have been politically. Moreover, by restricting suffrage, democracies replaced aristocracy by oligarchy.

Hence, I do not think that the surprise can be dated to 1750. In turn, viewed from the perspective of 1850, the coexistence of democracy with unequal distribution of property is hard to fathom. The syllogism according to which the poor would use their majority status to expropriate the rich was after all almost universally accepted. And it still makes logical sense today.

Just consider the favorite toy of political economists, the median voter model (Meltzer and Richards 1981): Each individual is characterized by an endowment of labor or capital and all individuals can be ranked from the poorest to the richest. Individuals vote on the rate of tax to be imposed on incomes generated by supplying these endowments to production. The revenues generated by this tax are either equally distributed to all individuals or spent to provide equally valued public goods, so that the tax rate uniquely determines the extent of redistribution. Once the tax rate is decided, individuals
maximize utility by deciding in a decentralized way how much of their endowments to supply. The median voter theorem asserts that there exists a unique majority rule equilibrium, this equilibrium is the choice of the voter with the median preference, and the voter with the median preference is the one with median income. And when the distribution of incomes is right-skewed, that is, if the median income is lower than the mean, as it is in all countries for which data exist, majority rule equilibrium is associated with a high degree of equality of post-?sc (tax and transfer) incomes, tempered only by the deadweight losses of redistribution. Moreover, the demand for social and economic equality persists. While elites see democracy in institutional terms, mass publics, at least in Eastern Europe and Latin America, conceive of it in terms of social and economic equality. In Chile, 59 percent of respondents expected that democracy would attenuate social inequalities (Alaminos 1991), while in Eastern Europe the proportion associating democracy with social equality ranged from 61 percent in Czechoslovakia to 88 percent in Bulgaria (Bruszt and Simon 1991). People do expect that democracy would breed social and economic equality. Hence,
the coexistence of democracy and inequality continues to be tense.

Yet income distribution appears to be amazingly stable over time. The strongest evidence, albeit for a relatively short period, comes from Li, Squire, and Zou (1997), who report that about 90 percent of total variance in the Gini coefficients is explained by the variation across countries, while few countries show any time trends. Longer time-series show that while income distribution became somewhat more equal in some democratic countries, redistribution was quite limited. These assertion are not contradictory: the main reason for equalization was that wars and major economic crises destroyed large fortunes and they could not be accumulated again because of progressive income tax. Earned incomes show almost no variation during the twentieth century. (For long-term dynamics of income distribution, see Piketty 2003 on France, Piketty and Saez 2003 on the United States, Saez and Veall 2003 on Canada, Banerjee and Piketty 2003 on India, Dell 2003 on Germany, and Atkinson 2002 on the United Kingdom.) It appears that there are no countries which equalized market incomes without some kind of cataclysm.

The cataclysms come in two kinds: (1) destruction of large property as a result of foreign occupation (Japanese in Korea, Soviet in Eastern Europe), revolution (Soviet Union), or war (France according to Piketty 2000), or (2) massive emigration of the poor (Norway, Sweden).

Since the issue is burning, explanations abound. Most assert that for a variety of reasons those without property, even if they constitute a vast majority in all known societies, either do not want to or cannot use their political rights to equalize property, incomes, or even opportunities. For reasons of space, I can only list the explanations of why the poor would not want to redistribute: (1) false consciousness due to a lack of understanding of the distinction between productive and non-productive property, (2) ideological domination due to the ownership of the media by the propertied, (3) difficulty of the poor to coordinate when they have some non-economic heterogeneous tastes, such as religion or race, (4) expectations that the poor would become rich, (5) the fact that taxes are palpable, while public spending is amorphous.

I am not taken by the idea that in general the poor would not want to lead better lives at the expense of the rich, but several arguments to the e¤ect that political rights are ineffective against private property make eminent sense.

Wealth holders enjoy disproportionate political influence, which they use to successfully defend themselves from redistribution (Benabou 2000).21 Nominally equal political rights do not seem to be enough to bar the privileged access of the rich to politics. Put differently, oblivion to economic differences is not sufficient to protect politics from the influence of money.

Yet this entire way of thinking confronts an awkward fact that many governments were elected with the support of the poor, wanted to equalize incomes, and tried to do so. Hence, to the extent to which they failed, it must have been for reasons other than not wanting or not trying. Here are some possible reasons:

(1) Redistributing productive property or even incomes is costly to the poor. Confronting the perspective of losing their property or not being able to enjoy its fruits, property owners save and invest less, thus reducing future wealth and future income of everyone. As Machiavelli observed, everybody is eager to acquire such things and to obtain property, provided that he be convinced that he will enjoy it when it has been acquired (Discourses on Livy. II.2, cited after Holmes 2003). Prospects of redistribution reduce investment. This structural dependence on capital (Przeworski and Wallerstein 1988) imposes a limit on redistribution even on those governments that want to equalize incomes. Hence, while some democratic governments do correct distributions of income generated by the unequal ownership of assets, equalizing assets ends up being a cataclysmic event, occurring only under exceptional circumstances.
(2) What are the assets that can be equalized in modern societies? Note that when the idea of equal property ?rst appeared productive assets meant land. Land is relatively easy to redistribute. It is enough to take it from some and give it to others. Hence, agrarian reforms were frequent in history of the world: according to data collected by Thomas (2005), there were at
least 175 land reforms entailing redistribution between 1946 and 2000 alone. But today the distribution of land plays a relatively minor role in generating income inequality. In turn, other assets resist such a simple operation. Communists redistributed industrial capital by turning it into the hands of the state and announcing that the uninvested pro?ts would be equally distributed to households. This solution engendered several negative consequences that need not be discussed. Alternatively, one could redistribute titles to property in the form of shares. But this form of redistribution has problems
of its own.22 Finally, one could, and many countries did, equalize human capital by investing in education. But people exposed to the same educational system acquire very di¤erent income earning capacities as a function of their social and economic background. Moreover, since people are born with different talents and since the use of these talents is socially bene?ficial,
we would want to educate talented people more. In sum, redistributing productive assets seems to be di¢ cult for purely technological, not just political or economic, reasons.
(3) Asking How laws establish equality in a democracy? the title of Chapter 5 of Book 5 Montesquieu takes as the point of departure equality of land. Then he goes on, If, when the legislator makes such a division, he does not give laws to maintain it, he only makes a passing constitution; inequality will enter from the side the laws do not defend, and the republic
will be lost.
Therefore, although real equality would be the soul of the state, it is so difficult to establish that an extreme rigor in this respect is not always convenient. It is sufficient, he continues, to reduce differences to some point, after which, it is for particular laws to equalize, to put it this way, the inequalities, by the charges they impose on the rich and the relief they accord to the poor. (1995: 151-5)

Remember that Babeuf believed that redistribution of property would not solve the problem of inequality, “since no equal division would ever last.

Suppose productive assets had been equalized. But individuals have different and unobservable abilities to transform productive assets into incomes.

Moreover, they are subject to vicissitudes of luck. Assume that particular individuals (or projects they undertake) are subject to slightly different rates of return: some lose at the rate of -0.02 and some gain at the rate 0.02. After 25 years, the individual who generates a 2 percent return will be 2.7 times wealthier than the individual who loses 2 percent per year, and after 50 years (say from the age of 18 to 68) this multiple will be 7.4. Hence, even if productive assets were to be equalize, inequality would creep back in. (The classical statement of this argument is by Pareto 1897, investigated recently by Mookherjee and Ray 2003 as well as Benhabib and Bisin 2007).

7 Judging Democracy

Analyzing the Thatcher era, Dunn (2000: 147) observes that “the state at this point is more plausibly seen as a structure through which the minimally participant citizen body (those prepared to take the trouble to vote) select from the meagre options presented to them those they hope will best serve their several interests. In that selection, the meagreness of the range of options is always important and sometimes absolutely decisive.” The issue is to what extent these choices are tightly circumscribed because the logic of electoral competition pushes political parties to o¤er and pursue similar policies and to what extent there is just little else they could do. The question is important because it affects our political judgment of democracy (On political judgment, see Dunn 2000 and the Introduction to this volume). Suppose that economic inequality could be diminished below the levels prevailing in developed democracies without reducing future incomes and that it is not being
diminished only because of the institutional features of democracy, however one thinks about them. Obviously, judging this trade-o¤ would depend on other values we would have to give up opting for equality. But there is no such trade-off.

Some degree of economic inequality is just inevitable. Democracy is impotent against it, but so is every other conceivable political arrangement.

Think of Brazil: during the past two centuries it was a royal colony, an independent monarchy, an oligarchical republic, a populist military dictatorship, democracy with a weak presidency, a right-wing military dictatorship, and democracy with a strong presidency. Yet, to the best of our knowledge, income distribution did not budge. Even the communists, who were out to
uravnit everything, and who did equalize assets in the form of public ownership, had to tolerate the inequality arising from different talents and motivations. Indeed, it turns out that the average household/individual income inequality is almost exactly the same in democracies and in non-democracies at each level of per capita income.

The quest for equality in the economic and social realm has been perpetual in democracies. The original blinders that modern representative institutions placed on economic and social standing of citizens could not effectively cover the glaring inequality of their life conditions. At least since Babeuf, not to speak of Marx, limiting equality to the political realm always seemed “illogical.” Moreover, if the right always feared that effective political equality would threaten property, the left knew that equality limited to the political realm cannot be sustained in the face of economic and social inequalities.

“Extending democracy from the political to the social realm” was not just a call for social justice but for making democracy effective in the political realm itself. But this quest may have its limits and the knowledge of these limits is essential to judge democracy.

This is not to say that all democracies are the same. I am not arguing in support of Pareto’s “law,” according to which income distribution remains the same whatever the institutional framework and in spite of progressive taxation. Among contemporary democracies, the ratio incomes of the top to the bottom quintile, which is perhaps the most intuitive measure of inequality, ranges from about 33 in Brazil to less than 6 in Finland, Belgium, Spain, and South Korea. Hence, we can compare and judge the choices parties offer to voters, as well as policies of particular governments. Moreover, since conflicts over distribution of opportunities, employment, and consumption are the bread and butter of democratic politics, we must be vigilant. But even
the best governments operate under limits not of their making. The ratio of 6 is still very large: it means that in a country with per capita income of $15,000 (about average for these countries in 2002, counted in 1995 PPP dollars), a member of the top quintile would have the income of $27,000, while a member of the bottom quintile $4,500. Most survey respondents in Spain and South Korea see such inequality as excessive. Yet perhaps this is just the extent to which any political system can equalize assets or incomes.

My point, thus, is that perhaps Dunn, and we all, put too much burden on democracy.

8 References

Aguilar Rivera, José Antonio.
Alaminos, Antonio. 1991. Chile: transición politica y sociedad. Madrid:
Centro de Investigaciones Sociologicas.
Atkinson, A.B. 2002. Top Incomes in the United Kingdom over the Twentieth Century. Unpublished.
Banerjee, Abhijit and Thomas Piketty. 2003. Top Indian Incomes, 1922-2000. Unpublished.
Bagehot, Walter. 1963. The English Constitution. Ithaca, NY: Cornell
University Press.
Beitz, Charles R. 1989. Political Equality. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Bénabou, Roland. 2000. Unequal Societies: Income Distribution and the Social Contract. American Economic Review 90: 96-129.
Benhabib, Jess, and Alberto Bisin. 2007. “The distribution of wealth: Intergenerational transmission and redistribute policies.”Working paper, Department of Economics, New York University.
Bernstein, Eduard. 1961. Evolutionary Socialism. New York: Schocken.

Bolivar, Simon. 1969. Escritos politicos. Edited by Graciela Soriano,
Madrid: Alianza Editorial.
Bruszt, László, and János Simon. 1991. Political Culture, Political and Economical Orientations in Central and Eastern Europe during the Transition to Democracy. Manuscript. Budapest: Erasmus Foundation for Democracy.
Burda, Andrzej. 1990. Charakterystyka postanowie´n konstytucji PRLz 1952r. In Konstytucje Polski: Studja monogra?czne zdziejów polskiego
konstytucjonalizmu. Warszawa: Pa´nstwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe. Vol. 2, Pages 344-376.
Collier, Simon and William F. Sater. 1996. A History of Chile, 1808-1994. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Collini, Stefan, Donald Winch and John Burrow. 1983. That Noble Science of Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Condorcet. 1986 [1785]. Essai sur l’application de l?analyse a la probabilité des décisions rendues a la pluralité des voix. In Sur les élections et autres textes. Textes choisis et revus par Olivier de Bernon. Paris: Fayard. Pages 9-176.
Crook, Malcom. 1996. Elections in the French Revolution. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Deininger, Klaus, and Lyn Squire. 1996. A New Data Set Measuring Income Inequality. World Bank Economic Review 10: 565-591.
Dell, Fabien. 2003. ?Top Incomes in Germany over the Twentieth Cen-
tury: 1891-1995.? Unpublished.
Dunn, John. 1993. ?Conclusion.? John Dunn (ed.), Democracy: The
Un?nished Journey, 508 BC to AD 1993. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Pages 239-266.
Dunn, John. 2000. The Cunning of Unreason: Making Sense of Politics.
London: HarperCollins.
Dunn, John. 2003. ?Democracy Before the Age of the Democratic Rev-
olution.?Paper delivered at Columbia University.
Dunn, John. 2005. Democracy: A History. New York: Atlantic Monthly
Press.
Dunn, Susan. 2004. Je¤erson?s Second Revolution: The Election Crisis
of 1800 and the Triumph of Republicanism. Boston: Houton Mi­ in.
Ensor, R.C.K. 1908. Modern Socialism as Set Forth by the Socialists in
Their Speeches, Writings, and Programmes. New York: Charles Scribner?s
Sons.

Ferejohn, John. 1995. ?Must preferences be respected in a democracy??
In David Coop, Jean Hampton, and John E. Roemer (eds.), The Idea of
Democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Pages 231-244.
Finer, Herman. 1934. The Theory and Practice of Modern Government.
New York: Dial Press.
Fontana, Biancamaria. 1993. ?Democracy and the French Revolution.?
In John Dunn (ed.), Democracy: The Un?nished Journey, 508 BC to AD
1993. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Pages 107-124.
Gargarella, Roberto. 2005. Los fundamentos legales de la desigualidad:
El constitucionalismo en América (1776-1860). Madrid: Siglo XXI.
Graetz, Michael J. and Ian Shapiro. 2005. Death by a Thousand Cuts:
The Fight over Taxing Inherited Wealth. Princeton: Princeton University
Press.
Grossman, Gene M. and Elhanan Helpman. 2001. Special Interest Poli-
tics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Gutiérrez Sanin, Francisco. 2003. ?La literatura plebeya y el debate
alrededor de la propriedad (Nueva Granada, 1849-1854).?In Hilda Sabato
(ed.), Ciudadanía política y formación de las naciones: Perspectivas históri-
cas de América Latina. Mexico: El Colegio de Mexico. Pages 181-201 .
Hanson, Russell L. 1985. The Democratic Imagination in America. Prince-
ton: Princeton University Press.
Hanson, Russell L. 1989. ?Democracy.? In Terence Ball, James Farr,
and Russell L. Hanson (eds.), Political innovation and conceptual change.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Pages 68-89.
Harrington, James. 1977. The Political Works of James Harrington,
edited by J.G.A.Pocock. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Holmes, Steven, 2003. ?Lineages of the Rule of Law.? In José María
Maravall and Adam Przeworski (eds.), Democracy and the Rule of Law. New
York: Cambridge University Press. Pages 19-61.
Jaures, Jean. 1971. L?Esprit de socialisme. Paris: Denoel.
Kant, Immanuel. 1891 [1793]. ?The Principles of Political Right,? in
Kant?s Principles of Politics. Edited and translated by W. Hardie, B.D.
Edinburgh: T&T. Clark.
Kelsen, Hans. 1988 [1929]. La Démocratie. Sa Nature-Sa Valeur. Paris:
Economica.
Ketcham, Ralph (ed.) 1986. The Anti-Federalist Papers and the Consti-
tutional Convention Debates. New York: Mentor Books.
Konopnicki, Guy. 1979. Vive le centenaire du P.C.F. Paris: CERF.

Kowecki, Jerzy. 1991. Konstytucja 3 Maja 1791. Warszawa. Pa´nstwowe
Wydawnictwo Naukowe.
Krukowski, Stanis?law. 1990. ?Ma?la Konstytucja z 1919 r.? In Konsty-
tucje Polski: Studja monogra?czne z dziejów polskiego konstytucjonalizmu.
Warszawa: Pa´nstwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe. Vol. 2, Pages 7-18.
Laslett, Peter. 1988. ?Introduction?to Locke. Two Treaties of Govern-
ment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Li, Hongyi, Lyn Squire and Heng-fu Zou. 1997. ? Explaining Interna-
tional and Inter-temporal Variations in Income Inequality? The Economic
Journal 108: 1-18.
Lloyd, Trevor. 1971. Su¤ragettes International. London: American Her-
itage Press.
Locke, John. 1988 [1689/90]. Two Treaties of Government. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Loveman, Brian. 1993. The Constitution of Tyranny: Regimes of Excep-
tion in Spanish America. Pittsburgh: Pittsburgh University Press.
Macaulay, Thomas B. 1900. Complete Writings, vol. 17. Boston and
New York: Houghton-Mi­ in.
Madison, James. 1982 [1788]. The Federalist Papers by Alexander Hamil-
ton, James Madison and John Jay. Edited by Gary Wills. New York: Ban-
tam Books.
Maier, Charles. 1975. Recasting Bourgeois Europe. Princeton: Princeton
University Press.
Manin, Bernard. 1997. The Principles of Representative Government.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Marx, Karl. 1844. On the Jewish Question. http://csf.colorado.edu/psn/marx/Archive/1844-
JQ
Marx, Karl. 1952 [1851]. Class Struggles in France, 1848 to 1850.
Moscow: Progess Publishers.
Marx, Karl. 1934 [18xx]. The Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte.
Moscow: Progress Publishers.
Marx, Karl. 1971. Writings on the Paris Commune. Edited by H.Draper.
New York: International Publishers.
May, Kenneth O. 1952. ?A Set of Independent Necessary and Su¢ cient
Conditions for Simple Majority Decision.? Econometrica 20: 680-684.
Maza Valenzuela, Erika. 1995. ?Catolicismo, Anticlericalismo y la Ex-
tensión del Sufragio a la Mujer en Chile.? Estudios Politicos 58: 137-197.

Meltzer, Allan G and Scott F. Richards. 1981. ?A Rational Theory of
the Size of Government.? Journal of Political Economy 89: 914-927.
Michels, Roberto. 1962. Political Parties: A Sociological Study of the
Oligarchical Tendencies of Modern Democracies. New York: Collier Books.
Mill, John Stuart. 1991 [1857]. Considerations on Representative Gov-
ernment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Mill, John Stuart. 1989 [1859]. On Liberty and Other Writings. Edited
by Stefan Colini. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Montesquieu. 1995 [1748]. De l?esprit des lois. Paris: Gallimard.
Mookherjee, Dilip, and Debraj Ray, 2003. “Persistent Inequality.” Review
of Economic Studies 70: 369-393.
Nicolet, Claude. 1982. L?idée républicaine en France: Essai d?histoire
critique. Paris: Gallimard.
Orwell, George. 1946. The Animal Farm. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.
Palmer, R.R. 1959. The Age of the Democratic Revolution: vol. I. The
Challenge. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Palmer, R.R. 1964. The Age of the Democratic Revolution: vol. II. The
Struggle. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Pareto, Vilfredo. 1897. Cours d?Economie Politique. Vol. II. Lausanne:
F. Rouge.
Pasquino, Pasquale. 1996. ?Political Theory, Order, and Threat.? In Ian
Shapiro and Russell Hardin (eds.), Political Order. Nomos XXXVIII. New
York: New York University Press. Pages 19-41.
Pasquino, Pasquale. 1997. ?Emmanuel Sieyes, Benjamin Constant et le
?Gouvernement des Modernes?.? Revue Française de Science Politique 27:
214-229.
Pasquino, Pasquale. 1998. Sieyes et L?Invention de la Constitution en
France. Paris: Editions Odile Jacob.
Piketty, Thomas. 2003. ?Income Inequality in France, 1901-1998.? Jour-
nal of Political Economy 111: 1004-1042.
Piketty, Thomas and Emmanuel Saez. 2003. ?Income Inequality in the
United States, 1913-1998.? Quarterly Journal of Economics 118: 1-39.
Przeworski, Adam and Michael Wallerstein. 1988. ?Structural Depen-
dence of the State on Capital.? American Political Science Review 82:
Przeworski, Adam and Fernando Limongi. 1993. ?Political Regimes and
Economic Growth.? Journal of Economic Perspectives 7: 51-69.
Rosanvallon, Pierre. 1995. ?The History of the Word ?Democracy? in
France.? Journal of Democracy 5(4): 140-154.

Rosanvallon, Pierre. 2004. Le Modèle Politique Français: La société civile
contre le jacobinisme de 1789 á nos jours. Paris: Seuil.
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. 1964 [1762]. Du contrat social. Edited by
Robert Derathé. Paris: Gallimard.
Schmitt, Carl. 1993. Théorie de la Constitition. Traduit de l?Allemand
par Lilyane Deroche. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France.
Schorske, Carl E. 1955. German Social Democracy 1905-1917: The De-
velopment of the Great Schism. New York: Harper&Row.
Schumpeter, Joseph A. 1942. Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy.
New York: Harper&Brothers.
Sharp, Andrew. 1998. The English Levellers. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Sieyes, Emmanuel. 1970. Qu?est-ce que le tiers état? Edited by Roberto
Zapperi. Genève: Droz.
Sunstein, Cass.1995. ?Democracy and Shifting Preferences.? In David
Coop, Jean Hampton, and John E. Roemer (eds.), The Idea of Democracy.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Pages 196-230.
Tingsten, Herbert. 1973. The Swedish Social Democrats. Totowa: Bed-
minster Press.
Tocqueville, Alexis de. 1961 [1835]. De la démocratie en Amérique. Paris:
Gallimard.
Wootton, David. 1993. ?The Levellers.?In John Dunn (ed.), Democracy:
The Un?nished Journey, 508 BC to AD 1993. Oxford: Oxford University
Press. Pages 71-90.

The Eternal Return of the Elite

Vilfredo Pareto

http://it.wikipedia.org/wiki/Vilfredo_Pareto

This monograph first saw the light of day in 1901 and has been understood as a somewhat famous attempt at a non race-based understanding of ‘elitism’. The failure of this attempt to be either genuinely explanatory or entirely successful seems, by almost all accounts, to have been historically verified by fascisms repeated descent into racism. But, given the utter failure of the Fascist movements of the post World War II era to gain traction, one wonders if perhaps now Pareto can, at last, be given a fair hearing. One even wonders if Pareto is fairly characterized as a fascist.

Be that as it may, Pareto still might have much to teach us about the interactions of elites. According to Pareto, elites rise to power, maintain dominance, and then fall; but only if another elite is struggling to take its place. (One is here reminded of Lenin’s remark against Trotsky, I believe, ‘that no state ever fell without being pushed’.) History is, according to this text, a circulation of elites; and for Pareto, the ideologies that these elites represent are only of secondary importance. What one must always keep in mind while reading this book is that, for Pareto, Liberals and Socialists (that is, the leaders of these ideological positions) are equally elites. By the ‘elite’, I should point out, Pareto always means the leadership of a class.

Pareto distinguishes between subjective and objective factors; the latter being real objects while the former are psychological states. Thus belief and unbelief are, for Pareto, equally psychological states. In fact, according to our author, belief is often the sign of a rising elite. Note that by ‘belief’ he doesn’t merely mean religious beliefs; according to Pareto socialism is a belief, that is, it is a psychological state. Indeed, for Pareto, perhaps somewhat surprisingly given his right-wing tendency and reputation, nationalism itself is also a belief. Now, he doesn’t propose to ignore these beliefs; on the contrary, it is the skepticism of the rulers towards beliefs that weakens them in the face of the rising elite. These ‘myths’ are a part of history and need to be explained.

The ‘religious sentiment’ (i.e., belief) of the masses is what leads to revolt. This sentiment is exploited by the rising elite in its attempt to overthrow the ruling elite. (In this matter the ‘skepticism’ of the ruling elite is no small aid to the rising elite.) And what we also need to keep in mind is that logical argument almost always fails in these matters; people believe for non-rational reasons, sentiment must be met with sentiment, i.e. socialism must be countered with nationalism. In fact, in these pages Pareto, over a hundred years ago, by describing the similarity between Christian and Socialist behavior, seems to indicate the possibility of a convergence of Christianity and Socialism vis-à-vis the ruling bourgeois. This possibility is currently being explored, thanks to the collapse of ‘really existing socialism’ in the USSR, by the most au courant leftist continental theory.

Keep in mind that, for Pareto, it is the ‘decadence’ (i.e., it is ‘less apt to defend its own power’) and the unabated rapacity of the old elite that causes it to perish. Indeed, he says of this decadence and rapacity that the old elite “could prosper if one of them were absent.” Scientifically, or so Pareto maintains, there really is nothing to choose between. Speaking of some historical examples of some crimes of new elites Pareto says, “The old elite, when it was in power, did even worse, so that one cannot conclude from these facts anything against one or the other regime…” Pareto simultaneously holds that reform is the most dangerous moment for the ruling elite, and that the waning of power is perfectly compatible with a rise in the use of violence. In fact, one comes away from this book feeling that the things that Pareto held in most contempt were inefficiency and incompetence and, indeed, some of his most contemptuous gestures in this matter are reserved for the capitalists.

In any case, the problem seems to be that the falling class, no longer believing in itself, can no longer attract the best young people to its cause. The rising class has ‘belief’ and hope, the falling one only has its privileges. Persecution seems to be no remedy for this. Indeed, thanks to persecutions, “many people of doubtful loyalty and unsteady character were eliminated and professional politicians kept away.” …Very amusing! But here, in 1901, Pareto sees the best of future generations going to socialism while all persecution does is prune the revolutionary plant.

In fact, if one carries away anything from this book it is that old elites must eventually fall. We learn here that socialism is the heir of Christian ‘belief’. And since Christianity is dying, all the old elite can do is delay the inevitable ‘homecoming’ of the common people (and their ‘religious sentiment’) to socialism. Thus ‘belief’ replaces ‘belief’. Again, there is little rationality in this process; Pareto is at pains to emphasize the ‘subjective phenomenon’. This is why nationalism is the best answer to socialism; one counters one irrationality with another.

This book is really only a long essay, the hardcover edition before me has 75 pages of text, 18 pages of notes, and a 22 page introduction. The notes are quite good and should not be passed up. For example, while nicely playing off his understanding of socialism as but another belief, Pareto, after discussing some socialist ‘sectarians’, writes, “One day we will perhaps have the Holy Inquisition of the socialist faith. (Note 18)” The Soviet ‘show trials’ of the thirties were indeed this Inquisition. This really is a superb book, a worthy companion piece to all the great political realists of history – from Machiavelli to Gramsci.

Vilfredo Pareto

http://it.wikipedia.org/wiki/Vilfredo_Pareto

This monograph first saw the light of day in 1901 and has been understood as a somewhat famous attempt at a non race-based understanding of ‘elitism’. The failure of this attempt to be either genuinely explanatory or entirely successful seems, by almost all accounts, to have been historically verified by fascisms repeated descent into racism. But, given the utter failure of the Fascist movements of the post World War II era to gain traction, one wonders if perhaps now Pareto can, at last, be given a fair hearing. One even wonders if Pareto is fairly characterized as a fascist.

Be that as it may, Pareto still might have much to teach us about the interactions of elites. According to Pareto, elites rise to power, maintain dominance, and then fall; but only if another elite is struggling to take its place. (One is here reminded of Lenin’s remark against Trotsky, I believe, ‘that no state ever fell without being pushed’.) History is, according to this text, a circulation of elites; and for Pareto, the ideologies that these elites represent are only of secondary importance. What one must always keep in mind while reading this book is that, for Pareto, Liberals and Socialists (that is, the leaders of these ideological positions) are equally elites. By the ‘elite’, I should point out, Pareto always means the leadership of a class.

Pareto distinguishes between subjective and objective factors; the latter being real objects while the former are psychological states. Thus belief and unbelief are, for Pareto, equally psychological states. In fact, according to our author, belief is often the sign of a rising elite. Note that by ‘belief’ he doesn’t merely mean religious beliefs; according to Pareto socialism is a belief, that is, it is a psychological state. Indeed, for Pareto, perhaps somewhat surprisingly given his right-wing tendency and reputation, nationalism itself is also a belief. Now, he doesn’t propose to ignore these beliefs; on the contrary, it is the skepticism of the rulers towards beliefs that weakens them in the face of the rising elite. These ‘myths’ are a part of history and need to be explained.

The ‘religious sentiment’ (i.e., belief) of the masses is what leads to revolt. This sentiment is exploited by the rising elite in its attempt to overthrow the ruling elite. (In this matter the ‘skepticism’ of the ruling elite is no small aid to the rising elite.) And what we also need to keep in mind is that logical argument almost always fails in these matters; people believe for non-rational reasons, sentiment must be met with sentiment, i.e. socialism must be countered with nationalism. In fact, in these pages Pareto, over a hundred years ago, by describing the similarity between Christian and Socialist behavior, seems to indicate the possibility of a convergence of Christianity and Socialism vis-à-vis the ruling bourgeois. This possibility is currently being explored, thanks to the collapse of ‘really existing socialism’ in the USSR, by the most au courant leftist continental theory.

Keep in mind that, for Pareto, it is the ‘decadence’ (i.e., it is ‘less apt to defend its own power’) and the unabated rapacity of the old elite that causes it to perish. Indeed, he says of this decadence and rapacity that the old elite “could prosper if one of them were absent.” Scientifically, or so Pareto maintains, there really is nothing to choose between. Speaking of some historical examples of some crimes of new elites Pareto says, “The old elite, when it was in power, did even worse, so that one cannot conclude from these facts anything against one or the other regime…” Pareto simultaneously holds that reform is the most dangerous moment for the ruling elite, and that the waning of power is perfectly compatible with a rise in the use of violence. In fact, one comes away from this book feeling that the things that Pareto held in most contempt were inefficiency and incompetence and, indeed, some of his most contemptuous gestures in this matter are reserved for the capitalists.

In any case, the problem seems to be that the falling class, no longer believing in itself, can no longer attract the best young people to its cause. The rising class has ‘belief’ and hope, the falling one only has its privileges. Persecution seems to be no remedy for this. Indeed, thanks to persecutions, “many people of doubtful loyalty and unsteady character were eliminated and professional politicians kept away.” …Very amusing! But here, in 1901, Pareto sees the best of future generations going to socialism while all persecution does is prune the revolutionary plant.

In fact, if one carries away anything from this book it is that old elites must eventually fall. We learn here that socialism is the heir of Christian ‘belief’. And since Christianity is dying, all the old elite can do is delay the inevitable ‘homecoming’ of the common people (and their ‘religious sentiment’) to socialism. Thus ‘belief’ replaces ‘belief’. Again, there is little rationality in this process; Pareto is at pains to emphasize the ‘subjective phenomenon’. This is why nationalism is the best answer to socialism; one counters one irrationality with another.

This book is really only a long essay, the hardcover edition before me has 75 pages of text, 18 pages of notes, and a 22 page introduction. The notes are quite good and should not be passed up. For example, while nicely playing off his understanding of socialism as but another belief, Pareto, after discussing some socialist ‘sectarians’, writes, “One day we will perhaps have the Holy Inquisition of the socialist faith. (Note 18)” The Soviet ‘show trials’ of the thirties were indeed this Inquisition. This really is a superb book, a worthy companion piece to all the great political realists of history – from Machiavelli to Gramsci.

The Charter of the Forest

The world is full of willing people, some willing to work, the rest willing to let them. ? Robert Frost And that is the very problem with socialism. The same can be said with property of capitalism. One should not … Continue reading

The world is full of willing people, some willing to work, the rest willing to let them.
? Robert Frost

And that is the very problem with socialism. The same can be said with property of capitalism. One should not get hanged on labels.

Once the rules are set, human beings will be able to follow the letter while circumventing their spirit in search of personal gain.

Independently of government ideology there are always three classes in society: upper, middle, and lower. And the real purpose of government is to protect the prerogatives of the upper class. Change always comes from the middle class trying to take over the upper class and the lower class is cannon fodder for both.

Labels are a tool used to herd people. The essential thing for democracy and freedom is not the ideology, but the existence of check and balances to limit the power of the government. There are socialist democracies and autocratic capitalist regimes. A country like Canada, for example, with a more socialist government than the States, has a gentler society than the US.

Freedom and democracy peaked in the US in the late 1930s and are nowadays in decline.

The dichotomy Capitalism/Socialism is actually dated. In the USA the term socialism, let alone communism, is used solely as a pejorative term to discredit individuals and ideas, often arbitrarily. If one understands socialism as government control of the economy, all, 100%, of the world’s governments, even Republican’s are socialist to some degree.

There is a confusion of capitalism with the American worship of the individual and the nuclear family. It might be argued that these ideas are related but they are different and independent. According to the American work ethic you only get what you work for, and those who are willing to work will succeed and those who are willing to let them will not; but this is not what Capitalism is. For example, the German government of World War II was a rabid anticommunist capitalist regime that despised the individual.

Capitalism is the idea that market forces, carried out by intelligent agents looking for profit (self interest), let by themselves will generate wealth and prosperity for society as a whole. From this perspective the ideal government is indeed one with zero regulations and that concentrates in providing security and guaranteeing social order, without levying taxes.

Down the road only a few generations, the millennium of Magna Carta, one of the great events in the establishment of civil and human rights, will arrive. What we do right now, or fail to do, will determine what kind of world will greet that event. It is not an attractive prospect if present tendencies persist — not least, because the Great Charter is being shredded before our eyes.

The first scholarly edition of Magna Carta was published by the eminent jurist William Blackstone. It was not an easy task. There was no good text available. As he wrote, “the body of the charter has been unfortunately gnawn by rats” — a comment that carries grim symbolism today, as we take up the task the rats left unfinished.

Blackstone’s edition actually includes two charters. It was entitled The Great Charter and the Charter of the Forest. The first, the Charter of Liberties, is widely recognized to be the foundation of the fundamental rights of the English-speaking peoples.

The significance of the companion charter, the Charter of the Forest, is no less profound and perhaps even more pertinent. The Charter of the Forest demanded protection of the commons from external power. The commons were the source of sustenance for the general population: their fuel, their food, their construction materials, whatever was essential for life. The forest was no primitive wilderness. It had been carefully developed over generations, maintained in common, its riches available to all, and preserved for future generations — practices found today primarily in traditional societies that are under threat throughout the world.

The Charter of the Forest imposed limits to privatization. The Robin Hood myths capture the essence of its concerns (and it is not too surprising that the popular TV series of the 1950s, “The Adventures of Robin Hood,” was written anonymously by Hollywood screenwriters blacklisted for leftist convictions). By the seventeenth century, however, this Charter had fallen victim to the rise of the commodity economy and capitalist practice and morality.

The rise of capitalist practice and morality brought with it a radical revision of how the commons are treated, and also of how they are conceived. The prevailing view today is captured by Garrett Hardin’s influential argument that “freedom in a commons brings ruin to us all,” the famous “tragedy of the commons”: what is not owned will be destroyed by individual avarice.

An international counterpart was the concept of terra nullius, employed to justify the expulsion of indigenous populations in the settler-colonial societies of the Anglosphere, or their “extermination,” as the founding fathers of the American Republic described what they were doing, sometimes with remorse, after the fact. According to this useful doctrine, the Indians had no property rights since they were just wanderers in an untamed wilderness. And the hard-working colonists could create value where there was none by turning that same wilderness to commercial use.

In reality, the colonists knew better and there were elaborate procedures of purchase and ratification by crown and parliament, later annulled by force when the evil creatures resisted extermination.

The grim forecasts of the tragedy of the commons are not without challenge. The late Elinor Olstrom won the Nobel Prize in economics in 2009 for her work showing the superiority of user-managed fish stocks, pastures, woods, lakes, and groundwater basins. But the conventional doctrine has force if we accept its unstated premise: that humans are blindly driven by what American workers, at the dawn of the industrial revolution, bitterly called “the New Spirit of the Age, Gain Wealth forgetting all but Self.”

Popular struggles to bring about a freer and more just society have been resisted by violence and repression, and massive efforts to control opinion and attitudes. Over time, however, they have met with considerable success, even though there is a long way to go and there is often regression. Right now, in fact.

The most famous part of the Charter of Liberties is Article 39, which declares that “no free man” shall be punished in any way, “nor will We proceed against or prosecute him, except by the lawful judgment of his peers and by the law of the land.”

The capitalist model has exhausted its usefulness because in its implementation requires a consumption society with infinite resources and relentless growth. I recommend to check the site Do the Math by a UCSD Physics professor and start with the article about the irrationality of this way of thinking (http://physics.ucsd.edu/do-the-math/2012/04/economist-meets-physicist/).

Fabian Society

The United States was not always a Progressivist nation. The beginning of Our Progressive Century started in Europe with the Iron Chancellor, Otto von Bismarck, where long-repressed German socialism began to blossom and give birth to organized labor and militant class warfare … Continue reading

The United States was not always a Progressivist nation.

The beginning of Our Progressive Century started in Europe with the Iron Chancellor, Otto von Bismarck, where long-repressed German socialism began to blossom and give birth to organized labor and militant class warfare on the continent. The Russian Revolution was still on the horizon. And the sun never set on the British Empire.

Non-native Progressivism was imported to the U.S. at the same time as socialism began to infect the entire world. Perhaps the most instrumental purveyors of the new thinking were members of the socialistFabian Society, founded in 1884 by Frank Podmoreand Edward Pease. Fabians believe in the slow, incremental progress of socialism. Over time, Fabian Society members founded what are now considered main-stream institutions such as the London School of Economics and the British Labour Party. The society is very active to this day.

Its members have included George Bernard Shaw (before AlGore, the only winner of both the Nobel Peace Prize and an Oscar), the author and friend-of-Teddy H.G. Wells, the short-term thinker and legendary economist John Maynard Keynes, the long-serving “Third Way” ex-Prime Minister Tony Blair, and the current Prime Minister Gordon Brown.

The Fabian Society is a British socialist organization whose purpose is to advance the principles of democratic socialism via gradualist and reformist, rather than revolutionary, means.[1][2] It is best known for its initial ground-breaking work beginning late in the 19th century and continuing up to World War I. The society laid many of the foundations of the Labour Party and subsequently affected the policies of states emerging from the decolonisation of the British Empire, especially India.

The Fabian Society was founded on 4 January 1884 in London as an offshoot of a society founded in 1883 called The Fellowship of the New Life.[3] Fellowship members included poets Edward Carpenter and John Davidsonsexologist Havelock Ellis and the future Fabian secretary Edward R. Pease. They wanted to transform society by setting an example of clean simplified living for others to follow, but when some members also wanted to become politically involved to aid society’s transformation, it was decided that a separate society, the Fabian Society, also be set up. All members were free to attend both societies. The Fabian Society additionally advocated renewal of Western European Renaissance ideas and their promulgation throughout the rest of the world.

The Fellowship of the New Life was dissolved in 1899,[4] but the Fabian Society grew to become the pre-eminent academic society in the United Kingdom in theEdwardian era, typified by the members of its vanguard Coefficients club. Public meetings of the Society were for many years held at Essex Hall, a popular location just off the Strand in central London.[5]

The Fabian Society, which favoured gradual change rather than revolutionary change, was named – at the suggestion of Frank Podmore – in honour of theRoman general Fabius Maximus (nicknamed “Cunctator”, meaning “the Delayer”). His Fabian strategy advocated tactics of harassment and attrition rather than head-on battles against the Carthaginian army under the renowned general Hannibal.

An explanatory note appearing on the title page of the group’s first pamphlet declared:

“For the right moment you must wait, as Fabius did most patiently, when warring against Hannibal, though many censured his delays; but when the time comes you must strike hard, as Fabius did, or your waiting will be in vain, and fruitless.”[6]

Immediately upon its inception, the Fabian Society began attracting many prominent contemporary figures drawn to its socialist cause, including George Bernard ShawH. G. WellsAnnie BesantGraham WallasHubert BlandEdith NesbitSydney OlivierOliver LodgeLeonard Woolf and Virginia Woolf,Ramsay MacDonald and Emmeline Pankhurst. Even Bertrand Russell briefly became a member, but resigned after he expressed his belief that the Society’s principle of entente (in this case, between countries allying themselves against Germany) could lead to war.

At the core of the Fabian Society were Sidney and Beatrice Webb. Together, they wrote numerous studies[7] of industrial Britain, including alternative co-operative economics that applied to ownership of capital as well as land.

The first Fabian Society pamphlets[8] advocating tenets of social justice coincided with the zeitgeist of Liberal reforms during the early 1900s. The Fabian proposals however were considerably more progressive than those that were enacted in the Liberal reform legislation. The Fabians lobbied for the introduction of a minimum wage in 1906, for the creation of a universal health care system in 1911 and for the abolition of hereditary peerages in 1917.

Fabian socialists were in favour of reforming Britain’s imperialist foreign policy as a conduit for internationalist reform and a welfare state modelled on theBismarckian German model; they criticised Gladstonian liberalism both for its individualism at home and its internationalism abroad. They favoured a nationalminimum wage in order to stop British industries compensating for their inefficiency by lowering wages instead of investing in capital equipment; slum clearances and a health service in order for “the breeding of even a moderately Imperial race” which would be more productive and better militarily than the “stunted, anaemic, demoralised denizens…of our great cities”; and a national education system because “it is in the classrooms…that the future battles of the Empire for commercial prosperity are already being lost”.[10]

In 1900 the Society produced Fabianism and the Empire, the first statement of its views on foreign affairs, drafted by Bernard Shaw and incorporating the suggestions of 150 Fabian members. It was directed against the liberal individualism of those such as John Morley and Sir William Harcourt.[11] It claimed that the classical liberal political economy was outdated, and that imperialism was the new stage of the international polity. The question was whether Britain would be the centre of a world empire or whether it would lose its colonies and end up as just two islands in the North Atlantic. It expressed support for Britain in the Boer War because small nations, such as the Boers, were anachronisms in the age of empires.[11] In order to hold onto the Empire, the British needed to fully exploit the trade opportunities secured by war; maintain the British armed forces in a high state of readiness to defend the Empire; the creation of a citizen army to replace the professional army; the Factory Acts would be amended to extend to 21 the age for half-time employment, so that the thirty hours gained would be used in “a combination of physical exercises, technical education, education in civil citizenship…and field training in the use of modern weapons”.[12]

The Fabians also favoured the nationalisation of land rent, believing that rents collected by landowners were unearned, an idea which drew heavily from the work of American economist Henry George.

Many Fabians participated in the formation of the Labour Party in 1900 and the group’s constitution, written by Sidney Webb, borrowed heavily from the founding documents of the Fabian Society. At the Labour Party Foundation Conference in 1900, the Fabian Society claimed 861 members and sent one delegate.

In the early 1900s Fabian Society members advocated the ideal of a scientifically planned society and supported eugenics by way of sterilization. This is credited to the passage of the Half-Caste Act, and its subsequent implementation in Australia, where children were systematically and forcibly removed from their parents, so that the British colonial regime could “protect” the Aborigine children from their parents. In an article published in The Guardian on 14 February 2008, (following the apology offered by Australian prime minister Kevin Rudd to the “stolen generations“),Geoffrey Robertson criticised Fabian socialists for providing the intellectual justification for the eugenics policy that led to the stolen generations scandal.[29][30] Such views on socialism, inequality and eugenics in early 20th century Fabians was not limited to one individual, it was a widely shared view in Fabian Society.

Socialism

Socialism is an economic system characterized by social ownership of the means of production and co-operative management of the economy,[1] and apolitical philosophy advocating such a system. “Social ownership” may refer to cooperative enterprises, common ownership, state ownership, or citizen ownership of equity.[2] There are many varieties of socialism and there is no single definition … Continue reading

Socialism is an economic system characterized by social ownership of the means of production and co-operative management of the economy,[1] and apolitical philosophy advocating such a system. “Social ownership” may refer to cooperative enterprises, common ownershipstate ownership, or citizen ownership of equity.[2] There are many varieties of socialism and there is no single definition encapsulating all of them.[3] They differ in the type of social ownership they advocate, the degree to which they rely on markets or planning, how management is to be organised within productive institutions, and the role of the state in constructing socialism.[4]

A socialist economic system would consist of a system of production and distribution organized to directly satisfy economic demands and human needs, so that goods and services would be produced directly for use instead of for private profit[5] driven by the accumulation of capital. Accounting would be based onphysical quantities, a common physical magnitude, or a direct measure of labour-time in place of financial calculation.[6][7] Distribution would be based on the principle to each according to his contribution.

As a political movement, socialism includes a diverse array of political philosophies, ranging from reformism to revolutionary socialism. Proponents of state socialism advocate the nationalisation of the means of production, distribution and exchange as a strategy for implementing socialism. In contrast, libertarian socialism proposes the traditional view of direct worker’s control of the means of production and opposes the use of state power to achieve such an arrangement, opposing both parliamentary politics and state ownership. Democratic socialism seeks to establish socialism through democratic processes and propagate its ideals within the context of a democratic political system.

Modern socialism originated from an 18th-century intellectual and working class political movement that criticised the effects of industrialisation and private property on society. In the early 19th-century, “socialism” referred to any concern for the social problems of capitalism irrespective of the solutions to those problems. However, by the late 19th-century, “socialism” had come to signify opposition to capitalism and advocacy for an alternative system based on some form of social ownership.[8] Marxists expanded further on this, attributing scientific assessment and democratic planning as critical elements of socialism. In the late 20th century, the term “socialist” has also been used by Third way social democrats to refer to an ethical political doctrine focusing on a common set of values emphasizing social cooperation, universal welfare, and equality